In the Beginning
Was the Deed
A Neo-Girardian Look at the Passion Narratives
==================
René Girard: Doing Sacred Violence to the Text?
A form-critical
study of dust jacket blurbs and book reviews might reveal that the most
often used concluding line is "Even if one finds he cannot agree with
Dr. Frankenstein's thesis, one must take it seriously." A rhetorical
analysis would make it plain that such a line is a euphemistic damning
with faint praise. The point seems to be "He's crazy, but he did
put a lot of work into it." And yet when one reads Burton Mack's
assessment of the work of René Girard, "Many biblical scholars will be
troubled by Girard's theory... But none will be able to... avoid his
challenge" (Mack, 137), one cannot help feeling that this time he means
it. In Lukan terms, Girard's theory of mimetic violence and the
scapegoat mechanism have become "a sign spoken against... that thoughts
out of many hearts may be laid bare." His hermeneutic of suspicion
forces us to rethink the basic character of religion itself, and not
just of conventional interpretations of texts. Indeed the challenge of
Girard is so wide-ranging that I can take up but the tiniest fragment
here. The rest I will gladly leave to the ranks of dissertation writers.
Basically what I intend to do is,
first, to summarize Girard's main thesis in broad outline, then to
indicate where his own application of it to the Gospels seems to go
astray, and finally to suggest some results of a consistent application
of the Girardian paradigm to the Gospels. In Girard's own terms (see
immediately below) I will be engaging in a mimetic rivalry with Girard
himself as my rival, seeking to emulate his method but to do his trick
better than he does. Why not?
Let Not Your Left Hand Know...
René Girard's theories are set forth
in a series of books including Deceit, Desire, and the Novel
(originally published, in French, in 1961), Violence and the Sacred
(1972), Things Hidden Since the Foundation of the World (1978),
"To Double Business Bound" (1978), The Scapegoat (1982),
Job, the Victim of his People (1985), and Violent Origins:
Ritual Killing and Cultural Formation (with Walter Burkert and
Jonathan Z. Smith, edited by Robert G. Hamerton-Kelly, 1987). For the
beginning Girardian, Violence and the Sacred or The Scapegoat
ought to be adequate to give a good, detailed impression of the theory.
His hypothesis is that all culture, civilization, political order,
cultural forms, and most especially all religion began with the violent
resolution of a primordial Hobbesian "war of all against all." That
resolution took the form of the collective murder of an arbitrarily
chosen scapegoat upon whom all hatred and blame might be focused and so
eliminated. "Cast out the scorner, and dissension will go out" (Proverbs
22:10). This originary act of violence may be repeated as needed when
the social/religious order created after the first scapegoat murder
begins to weaken and give way in a time of "sacrificial crisis." Order
will then be restored or reinforced, chaos held at bay. And though the
saving act of murder is ever and again re-presented in the form of
ritual sacrifice, the true nature of the deed as the frenzy of a lynch
mob will be hidden away under various mythic and theological veils. The
one sacrificed becomes a divine savior whose death was voluntary
obedience to the divine plan. In this way violence is reified and
mystified. Girard stands in the tradition of Durkheim, who characterized
religion as simply a mystification of social existence. The
mystification provides a transcendent sanction for the society's laws
and mores. Both the carrot and the stick are made more effective in this
way. Girard has, so to speak, taken Durkheim's theory farther in
explaining how social systems began and why it should be that religion
is the fright mask society wears. Concrete fears of mundane dangers are
here magnified to the proportions of Rudolf Otto's "numinous" fear of
the Mysterium Tremendum, fear of the dissolution of all things.
If the sanctions of the Sacred are not obeyed, the dam will collapse and
Chaos and Old Night will rampage again.
Though Girard is unclear about the
conditions obtaining before the initial crisis, his theory seems to
imply that most primitive collectivities began as peaceful anarchies.
But probably before too long, trouble began, as the Cain and Abel myth
indicates. The trouble was mimetic desire. Girard theorizes that desire
is always a function of one's imitation of another as a model. One
begins wanting to emulate another, perhaps a parent. Naturally, one
begins to desire what the model desires, simply in order to be like the
model. One imitates the tastes and the values of the model. But at some
point the object of desire becomes an obstacle between model and
imitator (or "disciple"). They cannot both have it. And at that point
model and imitator become rivals. Soon the desired object becomes
irrelevant, because the focus again becomes obviously what it already
was implicitly: it is the model himself that the imitator covets.
Casting aside his own being, the disciple seeks to gain justification,
real being, from the model who already has it (cf. Eric Hoffer, The
True Believer). The disciple seeks no longer to be like the
model but actually to become, to supplant, the model.
Striking contemporary examples of this phenomenon would be the many
cases of a fan who idolizes a celebrity to the point of stalking him or
her and finally killing the celebrity, as if in so doing, the fan could
supplant the idol/rival. Mark David Chapman was the mimetic rival of
John Lennon. Or think of Rupert Pupkin in The King of Comedy. Or
of Edward Nigma, mimetic rival/double of Bruce Wayne.
As already anticipated, such mimetic
conflict rapidly becomes violent. Sometimes violence thus spreads
throughout society, and we have the war of all against all. Bergman's
film Shame illustrates this condition. So do current events in
Bosnia and Serbia. In any case of mimetic violence, whether between two
antagonists or between whole countries, the mimetic rivals lose any real
distinction from one another. They become mimetic twins. No one is any
longer in the right or the wrong. Bosnia seems to us more sinned against
than sinning, but one must admit they have their own record of
atrocities to place beside Serbia's. Who could support either the
Sandinistas or the Contras with a clear conscience?
Since reciprocal violence has leveled
the playing field, it becomes not only impossible but also meaningless
for either party to admit to being at fault. So how can the turmoil
cease? The crowd suddenly seizes on someone, either a third party,
someone marginal to the society, or any one of the faceless figures in
the general melee, and puts him or her (or them--it might be a minority
ethnic or religious group) up as the secret culprit. This scapegoat has
become the "monstrous double" of all involved in the conflict. In this
figure they see their own rage and culpability, and they see it writ
large. And since all distinctions have been obliterated, they are not
strictly speaking wrong in seeing the guilt any place, in any face,
they look. But the person chosen must be marginalized or otherwise
insignificant since otherwise the victim's partisans will take revenge
for his death, and the cycle of reciprocal violence will continue
unabated.
The antagonists call a halt to the
fighting, forming a united front against the one now perceived as the
real culprit. The hapless scapegoat takes the blame. (One might
understand Mahatma Gandhi to have acted as a self-chosen scapegoat when
he undertook a "punishing" hunger strike to stop the Hindu-Muslim
rioting in newly independent
India.)
The scapegoat must have created the
whole mess by some secret and insidious means, an apple of discord
tossed in when no one was looking, a poisoner of the well of good will.
If the evil schemer can be done away with, everything ought to return to
normal. He dies. It does. The crashing silence of newly-won equilibrium
seems almost miraculous. Everyone takes a second look at the scapegoat.
He must have been a powerful being indeed, not only to bewitch everyone
in the first place, but now to heal everyone by his stripes as well! A
single death brought peace, demolished the dividing wall that had kept
us apart. Whereas before the victim was judged a maleficent magician,
now he is seen as a beneficent savior. The scapegoat is retroactively
exonerated.
But where does the guilt then go?
Perhaps to the members of the community itself, having acted in tragic
ignorance. "We esteemed him stricken of God and afflicted, but it was
our transgressions that he bore." But that is a hard thing to accept. So
a secondary scapegoat may be identified. And all blame is put on him.
He's the one who deceived us into slaying the savior! Off with his
head! (Or it may be that, as Hyam Maccoby suggests in The Sacred
Executioner, the secondary scapegoat will receive exoneration, too.)
The community owes its peace and
order, the restoration of pecking orders, social classes and boundary
lines, to the death of the scapegoat. So the scapegoat is forever after
venerated by repeated sacrificial anamnesis. All we like sheep had gone
astray, but the savior brought us back together in one fold as a
compassionate shepherd who gave his life for his sheep. The "surrogate
victim" employed may be another human or an animal substitute, but
either way he is an actor in a Passion Play. By this expedient of
repeated sacrifice the danger of chaos is recalled as well as the means
of its stemming. The social order is periodically reinforced, and people
are warned never to rock the boat again.
Only the saving deed is recalled in a
mythically revised form, one in which no real blame is attached to the
community, at least not for the arbitrary act of mob violence that put
out the fire. It must be so, because if the facts were to become known,
the illusion of mystification would be stripped away. All transcendent
reference with its powerful sanctioning function, would be gone. There
would not be sufficient fear if the sacred categorical imperative were
to be reduced to a merely prudential hypothetical imperative. The nation
of Islam has more spectacular success in getting people off drugs than
do humanistic secular agencies. "Pay no attention to the man behind the
curtain." So the effectiveness of the whole system depends on the
participants and beneficiaries not knowing how and why it works.
But Girard knows how it works. And he
believes he is able to discern in various myths and rituals the effaced
signs of the originary mob violence that secretly makes the system work.
He is able to disclose "the figure in the carpet" (Henry James) by a
sharp-eyed scrutiny. As Elisabeth Schüssler Fiorenza (41) says, Girard
has learned to listen to the silences of the mythic texts, aware that
they are often more eloquent than the words. "There is no speech, nor
are there words; their voice is not heard, yet their voice goes out
through all the earth, and their words to the end of the world" (Psalm
19:3-4).
In his analyses of myths Girard is
aided by insights derived from two other genres, the Classical tragedy
and the persecution text. A persecution text is the record of
scapegoating written by the persecutors in historical times (his
favorite example is Guillaume de Machaut's Judgment of the King of
Navarre, fourteenth century). It may credulously record how the
plague was brought to a halt by a pogrom, or how the burning of witches
put an end to an epidemic. The "double transference" whereby the
scapegoat is first laden with the guilt of the community and then
rehabilitated as a savior after his death, is represented in persecution
texts only up to the second transfer. The writer of a persecution text
still deems the Jew, the witch, the heretic as the guilty party. Good
riddance! So such texts offer us only a half-parallel to what Girard
envisions going on in myths. But, as far as it goes, Girard feels that
the persecution text does attest to the historical reality of the basic
scapegoating mechanism. By definition, the persecution text can go no
further toward depicting the second stage of transference than it
does.
And yet we may wonder whether Girard
does not undermine his own case when he suggests that we lack historical
texts depicting the second stage of transference because "Mythological
persecutors [are] more credulous than their historical equivalents" and
thus the latter are not to be expected to be sufficiently cowed by the
scapegoat's effectiveness as to deify and worship him (Girard, 1982,
50). This observation implies that we perhaps ought not to seek any
historical analogy to the postmortem transformation of the scapegoat,
that no historical plausibility attaches to this element of the myths.
(This is a significant and
embarrassing lacuna. But perhaps it may yet be filled. There might be
recent historical texts which do attest the second transformation,
though of course then they would no longer be persecution texts, not
that it matters. For instance, a Calvinist record of repentant
Calvinists erecting a monument to Michael Servetus, the non-trinitarian
Reformer whom Calvin burned at the stake, might qualify: Servetus, once
a detestable heretic, had now taken on the halo of a martyr even in the
eyes of those whose forbears had hounded him to death.)
Classical tragedies help to decode
myths because the dramatists have themselves begun to interpret the
myths and to rehistoricize them. It is they who fill in background
detail and color including socio-political and religious factors to
supply verisimilitude for their audiences. The tragedies, even when they
involved supernatural beings, had to seem plausible as happening in the
real world. In reconstructing, e.g., the political tensions surrounding
the tribulations of Oedipus, Sophocles was able, if not to restore the
actual events surrounding the originary act of violence Girard
postulates, then at least to tell us the kind of thing that would
have surrounded such events in his world. And once we learn what sort of
realities are apt to lie behind the myths, we can extrapolate in the
cases of those myths to which no dramatic counterpart survives. We will
know what to look for, what counts as a clue.
The actual process of reconstructing
the violent events underlying a myth involves a considerable amount of
cutting and pasting, juggling and reversing, and supplying elements
implicit in the myths. "They must be treated like pieces of a puzzle
which is the mimetic theory itself, once the correct arrangement has
been found" (Girard, 1982, 162). If Girard here sounds a bit like Claude
Levi-Strauss, he sounds even closer to him when he advises us to
disregard the original diegetic order of events in the myth: "The
relationship is then reversed. Differences cancel each other out; a
symmetry is constantly generated, invisible in each synchronic moment
taken separately but visible in the accumulation of moments... The same
details are reiterated throughout the story..., but never
simultaneously" (Girard, 1972, 245). "Mythology is a game of
transformations. Levi-Strauss has made a most important contribution in
revealing this... After shuffling his cards, the magician spreads them
out again in a different order. At first we have the impression that
they are all there, but is it true? If we look closer we shall see that
there is actually always one missing, and it is always the same one, the
representation of collective murder" (Girard, 1982, 73). "To be sure,
there are many details of the generative event that have dropped out,
many elements that have become so warped, misshapen, and transfigured as
to be unrecognizable when reproduced in mythical or ritualistic form"
(Girard, 1972, 310).
We recall both Levi-Strauss with his
paradigmatic approach and Vladimir Propp with his syntagmic approach
when we read Girard's analysis of Oedipus' actantial equivalence to
other characters in his story: "All the episodes of the Oedipus myth are
repetitions of one another... Oedipus, naturally, is a monster [a
parricide and engaging in incest], but Tiresias is a monster, too: as a
hermaphrodite... The sphinx is a monster... with its woman's head,
lion's body, [etc.]. On first glance there is a radical difference
between this imaginary creature and the human protagonists, but this
difference vanishes on closer inspection. The sphinx plays the same role
in relation to Oedipus as do all the human figures... Like Laius, like
the drunken Corinthian earlier in the story and Creon and Tiresias
later, the sphinx dogs Oedipus's tracks--whenever, that is, Oedipus is
not dogging the sphinx's tracks. Like the others, the sphinx catches
Oedipus in an oracular trap; in short, the episode of the sphinx
recapitulates the other episodes. The sphinx appears as the incarnation
of maleficent violence, as Oedipus himself will appear later on. The
sphinx has been sent by Hera to punish Thebes, just as the plague is
visited upon the city by order of Apollo... The episode of the sphinx
shows Oedipus in the role of monster-killer or executioner. Later a
monster himself, he will assume the role of surrogate victim. Like all
incarnations of sacred violence, Oedipus can and does play every part in
succession" (Girard, 1972, 252). Indeed, this is just the type of thing
we ought to expect in what Todorov calls a "narrative of substitutions"
following "ritual logic," one based on a sacred ritual, where there is
no linear development, only cyclical repetition. "The origin of the rite
is lost in the origin of time" (Todorov, 132).
Two examples highlighted in The
Scapegoat provide a good picture of Girard's methods in action. The
first is the Norse myth of the death of Balder. So beloved is the bright
hero of Asgard that his mother Frigga seeks to ensure his safety by
persuading every living thing never to harm Balder. They readily agree.
Unfortunately, Frigga has neglected to secure the oath of a young sprig
of mistletoe, which seemed already too harmless to threaten the divine
prince. One day Loki beholds his fellow Aesir at sport. They circle the
laughing Balder, throwing all manner of spears, swords, and javelins at
him. But all alike turn away at the crucial moment, unable to break
their vow of harmlessness. Loki dislikes to see such a spectacle and
calls for it to stop. Unheeded, he departs and wheedles from Frigga the
secret of the lone mistletoe sprig. This he finds and fashions into a
deadly dart. Placing it in the hand of Balder's blind brother Hother,
Loki guides his cast to its fatal target. Of course the myths of
Siegfried and Achilles come readily to mind.
But Girard smells something amiss.
Like a detective he is sure there is more than meets the eye here at the
crime scene. There must have been an earlier version of the myth in
which the encircling crowd of gods executed Balder, whom they regarded
as a culprit, by means of their firing squad. An initial clue is that in
the extant version Loki first tries to halt the game, as if he
anticipates a danger the others do not see. How then has he become the
villain of the piece? Note, too, the various "distancing devices" (Maccoby,
1982, 50, 97). We seem to have not only a primary scapegoat, Balder, but
a secondary scapegoat as well, Hother. And yet Hother himself is
exonerated, first, since he is blind, and thus may have landed the dart
accidentally, second, since he is ignorant, not knowing the secret of
the sprig until too late, and, third, in a subsequent retelling, since
it was the pestiferous Loki who put him up to it. Loki then becomes a
tertiary scapegoat!
The Greek myth of the infant Zeus and
the Curetes presents basically the same scenario. In it, the godling is
in danger from his hungry father Chronos. To hide him from the devourer,
the Curetes, fierce warriors, form a circle around the child. This
protective gesture, however, is enough to frighten baby Zeus, so he
begins to cry. To drown out the sound, the Curetes start crashing their
spears against their shields, raising a terrible din that frightens the
baby even more. The louder he bawls the louder they get, until Chronos
goes to find some peace and quiet elsewhere. Girard suspects that such a
commotion would be rather odd as a camouflage strategy. Originally it
must have meant something quite different. Of course, it must have been
a scene in which the Curetes themselves surrounded the divine babe and
closed ranks, slaughtering him. But later piety could not brook this, so
Chronos was brought on stage as the villain, while the Curetes became an
honor guard for the godling, surely a picture more in keeping with the
divine dignity.
But is such a myth of the collective
slaughter of a divine child really likely? Indeed it is, replies Girard,
since we have precisely such a myth still extant, in which the evil
Titans surround baby Dionysus (= "young Zeus", Murray, vi.) and
dismember him. Later Zeus takes revenge on the Titans and resurrects
Dionysus in another form. Perhaps this rescue is simply an alternative
way of cleaning up the deicidal myth. Here the original (human) lynch
mob has been translated into a group of culpable divinities. In the
myths of Zeus and the Curetes, the solution is the docetic one familiar
from early Christianity: there was no death. But Girard knows better. It
is written plainly between the lines. Perhaps in an intermediate version
of the myth the Curetes were trying to protect him, but Zeus was
killed, with Chronos as the secondary scapegoat, the noisy ruse having
failed. ("Hey! What in Hades is going on over there? Well, what
have we here?") In the same way, in the Balder myth the original
human slayers of the original human scapegoat were, like the Titans,
made into divinities, but innocent ones. Hence the need for a secondary
(and tertiary) scapegoat.
... What Your Right Hand Is Doing
The examples cited and discussed by
Girard are plentiful and well-argued. I find myself largely convinced in
most cases. At least I am eager to try the paradigm on for size. Thus,
again, I will not seek to defend the approach here. My goal is more
modest. I want to venture a consistent application of the Girardian
paradigm to the Gospel Passion texts. Obviously, I find Girard himself
coming up short at this point. At the end of Violence and the Sacred,
he writes, "No attempt will be made here to consider the Judeo-Christian
texts in the light of this theory, or vice versa; that must be left to a
future study. However, I hope to have suggested here the course that
such a project might take" (309). Though the anticipated study might
have taken the direction implied in Violence and the Sacred, in
fact it did not. Indeed, when one ventures into the pages of Things
Hidden Since the Foundation of the World and The Scapegoat,
one feels one has made a wrong turn somewhere, or that Girard has. In
these books Girard unfurls the banner of Christian apologetics,
specifically what I call dissimilarity apologetics.
We are told that the canonical
Gospels have once and for all called the bluff of the scapegoat
mechanism on which all previous religion rested, which all previous
mythology had embodied. It has done this by the simple expedient of
depicting Jesus as innocent, as being railroaded into his scapegoat
death. The very opposite of a persecution text, the Gospels are written
from the standpoint of the victim. Jesus even attacks the scapegoating
mechanism head-on, by damning the Jewish sacrificial system and calling
for the end of violence and counterviolence in favor of turning the
other cheek and loving the enemy. Jesus thus called for the end of the
mystification of violence as the Sacred. Granted, he sometimes had no
choice but to employ violent and sacrificial metaphors in order to have
any common ground with his hearers, and granted, this may be why it has
taken anyone this long to see what Jesus and the Gospels were getting
at. But there it is. And if we deny the results of his exegesis, we are
only continuing the conspiracy of sacred silence and forgetfulness that
has kept the cycle of controlled religious violence going all these
ages.
A growing group of Girardian
disciples has fanned out through the towns of academic Israel to spread
this word. Books written from Girard's perspective, promoting his
version of the nonviolent gospel, include Raymund Schwager, Must
There be Scapegoats? (1978, trans. 1987), James G. Williams, The
Bible, Violence, and the Sacred: Liberation from the Myth of Sanctioned
Violence (1991), Robert G. Hamerton-Kelly, Sacred Violence,
Paul's Hermeneutic of the Cross (1992) and The Gospel and the
Sacred, Poetics of Violence in Mark (1994), and Gil Bailie,
Violence Unveiled, Humanity at the Crossroads (1995). Burton Mack
("The Innocent Transgressor: Jesus in Early Christian Myth and History",
1985) and Lucien Scubla ("The Christianity of René Girard and the Nature
of Religion," 1985) have both undertaken detailed though somewhat
limited analyses of Girard's Gospel exegesis and found it severely
wanting. I agree: the Gospels seem to say what Girard says only if the
reader already belongs to that community of interpreters (Fish, 272)
infatuated with the Girardian kerygma. Hamerton-Kelly's exegesis of Mark
seems almost parodic, a case of hermeneutical ventriloquism at its
worst. Page after page of his work (and that of other Girardians) brings
inevitably to mind the pesher exegesis of the Dead Sea Scrolls.
Like scribes trained unto the kingdom of heaven, they are bringing
altogether new goods out of the old storehouse. When we observe this
sort of thing done by the New Testament writers, we are accustomed to
using the euphemism "charismatic exegesis." When we behold our own
colleagues indulging in the sport we call it, even more damningly,
"theological exegesis."
Indeed, as in Girard's own theory,
there is a crucial fact concealed from these exegetes which alone makes
their enterprise possible. They are like the Process Theologians of the
1970s who proclaimed Jesus the Christ because he had disclosed the
vision of what God is up to in the world: creative transformation. The
irony was, they had the wrong messiah. Surely Alfred North Whitehead
deserved the diadem! It was he, not Jesus, who first set forth the view
they espoused. No one would ever get Process Christology from the
Gospels as David Griffin (A Process Christology) and John Cobb (Christ
in a Pluralistic Age) did unless Whitehead had provided the esoteric
key. Even so, the revealer of the scapegoat mechanism is none other than
René Girard. Like the early Christian prophets posited by Bultmann,
Girard has put his own oracles on the lips of the historical Jesus.
Dissimilarity Apologetics
I have called Girard's handling of
the Gospels "dissimilarity apologetics." Here is what I have in mind.
Norman Perrin dubbed a widely used form-critical tool the "criterion of
dissimilarity." That is, the critic cannot be sure of the authenticity
of a Gospel logion unless it contradicts the beliefs of both
contemporary Judaism and the primitive church. Though Jesus may have
overlapped at many points with his Jewish contemporaries, and though the
early church may actually have taken him seriously here or there, we
will not know what was unique to the message of Jesus unless we employ
the criterion of dissimilarity. Behind this assumption lurks the
orthodox belief that Jesus must have had startlingly innovative things
to say since he was a divine revealer. And, not surprisingly, Perrin and
the others tended to exaggerate the differences between Judaism and
Jesus, making of Judaism an absurd caricature (as when Ebeling imagines
that the simple preaching of a loving God would have so infuriated
religious Jews as to goad them into executing Jesus! These are the
horned Jews of the Oberamergau Passion Play).
One can detect the same dissimilarity
apologetics in play today in two of the "hottest" subfields of New
Testament scholarship: feminist and social scientific criticism. Jewish
views and practices concerning women are distorted by selective
proof-texting of the Mishnah so that Jesus appears by contrast to have
been a radical proto-feminist. The Gospel evidence certainly shows that
Jesus was not a fanatical misogynist, for what that's worth. But it is
not hard to see him as fitting in with ordinary Judaism at this, as so
many other points. Why should this more modest verdict disappoint? I
suspect because the scholars in question think of Jesus as the divine
revealer, so he must have been at least as enlightened as themselves.
The approach is not unlike fundamentalist efforts to show that Genesis
chapter one really foretold the Big Bang or the sphericity of the
earth if you just read it the "right" way.
Social science critics take great
pains to construct a paradigm of Mediterranean peasant culture which
they assume must have held sway in Jesus' day. Once this paradigm is
employed in Gospel exegesis, many things are seen in a new light. But,
what do you know? It turns out that Jesus "radically reversed" or
"radically transcended" this or that social more. Just what one would
expect of the divine revealer. Someone has forgotten what it means to
use a paradigm. Paradigms are "surprise-free" (Kahn and Wiener, in
Berger, 16). If there is seemingly anomalous data that the model cannot
account for or would not have predicted, it must mean the paradigm needs
adjustment or replacement, or that we are misinterpreting the evidence.
One cannot use the paradigm against itself, as if a futurologist should
be so surprised at the appearance of an unforeseen trend as to declare
there had been a divine intervention in history. In my view, Girard and
his mimetic doubles have pulled the same cheat as these other
"dissimilarity apologists." If the Gospels appear to defy the type of
analysis Girard insists can decode all other supernatural tales as
scapegoat myths, then I am willing to bet that either Girard has buckled
his paradigm too tightly, or he is giving preferential treatment to a
particular set of myths--which just happen to be the scriptures of his
own personal religious faith.
It is a simple matter of shaving with
Occam's razor: if we find that the Gospel tales can after all be easily
accommodated by the method Girard uses to such effect on the myths of
Balder, Oedipus, Pentheus, the Curetes, and the infant Dionysus, then
why look any further? And it would seem that the Gospels fit the pattern
quite well. Yes, Jesus is depicted as innocent from the start,
railroaded and exploited as a scapegoat. But this is simply because
scapegoat myths are just the opposite of persecution texts. Persecution
texts only go up to the first transformation (that of the innocent into
the "monstrous double") because they are written by the persecutors who
still view the persecuted as the real culprits. But scapegoat myths
provide, not both stages of transformation as Girard implies, but rather
only the second. They do presuppose the first, but then that is what
Girard says we must coax out. The first transformation is never depicted
as such in the myths. Indeed, that is his whole point. What is (at least
sometimes) depicted is the subsequent transfiguration of the "evil"
scapegoat into a sanctified savior.
But often there is not even an
initial period of genuine culpability because the retroactive
sanctification of the scapegoat has completely permeated the myth. Here
one thinks of Küng's schema whereby the resurrection of Jesus
transformed him retroactively from a false prophet to the Messiah (344,
372-373; cf. Pannenberg, 135-136). Girard even recounts a number of
instances from current field observation in which sacred tribal kings
and condemned prisoners treated as kings for a day are venerated and
accorded special privileges even while they are blamed for all the
community's ills. This ambivalence, he explains, is the result of the
retrojection of their still-future sanctification into the present
(1972, 276-278, 302). How much more natural for this retrojection to
occur in the retelling of a myth? "As a community moves away from its
violent origins, ... moral dualism is reinforced. ... There comes a
time... when men want only models of morality and demand gods purified
of all faults... [Such desires] reflect the disintegration of the
primitive notion of the sacred, the tendency toward dualism that only
wants to maintain the beneficent aspect of the gods... The tendency to
idealize transforms or effaces all the stereotypes: the crisis, the
signs that indicate a victim, collective violence, and of course the
victim's crime. This can be seen clearly in the myth of Baldr. The god
who is not collectively killed cannot be a guilty god. He is a god whose
crime has been completely effaced, a perfectly sublime god, devoid of
all fault" (1982, 79). So why consider the Jesus story substantially
different from the Balder story? In both the divine hero is
unambiguously good and then slain by the machinations of a secondary
scapegoat figure.
"A guilty conscience is its own
accuser." Just so, Girard himself anticipates our protest: "The
uprooting [of the scapegoat mechanism] in the Gospels bears the same
relationship to the mythological conjuring tricks of a Baldr or the
Curetes as the complete removal of a tumor to a village quack's
'magnetic' tricks" (1982, 103). And yet on which side of this analogical
ratio does Jesus belong? Perhaps not the side Girard intends. "Jesus...
does as expected of a wandering magician" (Hamerton-Kelly, 1994, 101).
Girard seems to have learned a few Mesmeric conjuring tricks of his own.
Though he himself remarks, "Too great an effort to hide something always
reveals the deception" ( 1982, 69), there are many who do take Girard's
special pleading seriously, as we have seen. To them the difference
between scapegoat myths and the Gospels is (to borrow Hamerton-Kelly's
telling phrase) "stupefyingly clear" (1994, 68). Just as trivialities
seem profound to one under the influence of marijuana, so those under
Girard's spell have no trouble plumbing a difference where others may
not see a distinction.
In fact, elsewhere in the vast
Passion megatext, Maccoby is able to show startling parallels between
the Jesus and Balder Passions even to the details. For instance, in one
version of the Toledoth Yeschu, Judas has to display the dead
body of Jesus on a huge cabbage stalk instead of a cross or a
tree--since the sorcerer Jesus had, like Frigga, made all trees swear
an oath never to act against him! It is as if some recessive gene shared
by the two myths had at long last surfaced (1992, 98). Maccoby (1982,
49-51, 100-101) performs much the same sort of operation on the Gospel
story of Jesus on the analogy of Balder that we should have expected
Girard to perform. Mack does something similar: though he does not see
Jesus as a Girardian scapegoat, at length he concludes that the Gospels
are persecution texts scapegoating Jews (1985, 154-157).
Unlike Burton Mack, I do see the
Gospel Passion as a Girardian scapegoat myth. And while I agree with
Hyam Maccoby's analysis as far as it goes (and it does say the most
important thing), I will attempt to supply what the disappointed reader
of Girard has missed: a scrutiny of some specific features of the
Passion a la Girard's ingenious exegesis of the various pagan scapegoat
myths.
The Right Man at the Right Time
How does Jesus measure up as a
Girardian scapegoat? Does he betray any of the classic "signs of the
victim"? It seems he is quite suitable for the role. The scapegoat must
have an ambivalent relationship to the community. If he is not a member,
he cannot bear their guilt as a representative (cf.. Anselm's
Satisfaction theory of the atonement). On the other hand, he must be
somehow on the fringes of the community so as to be safe to pick on. His
collective murder must not engender reprisals or the cycle of reciprocal
violence will only continue. As many recent works suggest (Theissen,
1978, 1992; Downing, 1988, 1992; Crossan, 1991) Jesus is consistently
depicted in the Gospels as an itinerant preacher after the manner of
Elisha or the Cynics. He had no home or family, no possessions, roots,
or vested interests. Girard mentions how the scapegoat "passes freely
from the interior to the exterior and back again. Thus the surrogate
victim constitutes both a link and a barrier between the community and
the sacred" (1972, 271). Stevan Davies sums up the social position of
itinerants like Jesus: they visited settled communities but their
preaching contained no help for communities since the itinerant's ethos
inculcated individualistic asceticism. Such preaching would undermine
the community or fall on deaf ears. Thus itinerant prophets were
marginalized even among their own supporters (Davies, 36). That pretty
well fits Girard's characterization of the scapegoat.
Scott D. Hill ("The Local Hero in
Palestine in Comparative Perspective," 1992) demonstrates how itinerant
holy men have throughout history served as community mediators and
arbiters since people regarded them as both divinely inspired and
impartial, having no worldly interests (cf. Luke 12:13-14; Mark 12:14).
In this they were much like the living bodhisattvas of Mahayana Buddhism
whose sublime disinterest enabled them to have divine compassion on all
beings without favoritism. Girard shows how the scapegoat, while still a
"kind of pariah, assumes the role of supreme arbiter. In the event of an
irresolvable struggle he is called upon to 'differentiate' the
irreconcilable antagonists, thus proving that he incarnates the sacred
violence that is sometimes maleficent, sometimes beneficent" (1972,
262). And yet it is this very marginality that makes him the perfect
choice for the scapegoat: he belongs to neither side in the great
crisis, so his murder will not require retaliation. In a sense, as
Girard implies, his eventual death as a scapegoat is a kind of logical
extension and completion of his role as marginalized arbiter between two
disputing factions. Again, Jesus fills the role remarkably well.
There are more obvious marks of a
scapegoat. "We need only think of those social categories and
individuals that provide the victims in scapegoat rites--vagabonds,
beggars [both of these fit an itinerant prophet], cripples--to recognize
that derision of one form or another plays a large part in the negative
feelings that find expression in the course of the ritual sacrifice and
that are finally purified and purged by it" (1972, 254). Recall the
Hunchback of Notre Dame. (Cf. Erving Goffman, Stigma). To these
categories we might add membership in a minority or foreign group. The
crowd begins to intimidate Peter once they catch his Galilean accent
(Mark 14:70; Matthew 26:73). Jesus, too, was a Galilean in Judea. Was he
a cripple? Eastern Orthodox tradition made him hobble, one leg being
shorter than the other.
Girard does not limit massive
outbreaks of mimetic violence, requiring the antidote of collective
murder, to the dawn of human civilization. He says they continue to
erupt repeatedly throughout history whenever the sacrificial system
established by the previous crisis begins to break down. Violence is no
longer being "managed" in the proper sacerdotal channels. The difference
between "good" violence (that which proceeds along authorized channels
and at the hands of duly designated functionaries) and "bad" violence
(personal vendettas, rioting) has broken down. Girard recognizes that
sacrificial crises played an important role in the history of biblical
Israel. "Amos, Isaiah, and Micah denounce in vehement terms the
impotence of the sacrificial process and ritual in general. In the most
explicit manner they link the decay of religious practices to the
deterioration of contemporary behavior. Inevitably, the eroding of the
sacrificial system seems to result in the emergence of reciprocal
violence. Neighbors who had previously discharged their aggressions on a
third party, joining together in the sacrifice of an "outside" victim
[i.e., the sacrificial animals], now turn to sacrifice one another"
(1972, 43).
Signs of sacrificial crisis are
abundant in the gospels (and this much, of course, Girard would by no
means deny). We can see this most clearly in terms of the Jerusalem
temple cultus. Speaking of the sacrificial crisis in general, Girard
explains, "If the gap between the victim and the community grows too
wide, all similarity will be destroyed. The victim will no longer be
capable of attracting the violent impulses to itself; the sacrifice will
cease to serve as a 'good conductor,' in the sense that metal is a good
conductor of electricity" (1972, 39). Bruce Chilton (The Temple of
Jesus, His Sacrificial Program Within a Cultural History of Sacrifice,
1992) argues that what so disturbed Jesus about the temple sacrifices
was the fact that people no longer brought their own animals from home
to be sacrificed, but rather simply paid money for "government inspected
meat" once they got to the temple. And it wasn't even their own money
they used to pay for it! They had to change "idolatrous" Roman coins for
unfilthy lucre, without images. (I think it most likely that
Jesus refers to this practice when he dismisses the issue of whether
paying Roman tribute represents religious compromise, since the coin
used to pay the tax was a Roman coin that couldn't be used to buy
animals in the temple. Since you couldn't render your denarius to God
anyway, why not render it to Caesar?) Chilton has described
precisely a situation in which the distance between the offerer and his
sacrifice had grown too great for the sacrifice to be meaningful.
Sacrificial crisis, here we come.
Girard goes on to add: "On the other
hand, if there is too much continuity the violence will overflow
its channels. 'Impure' violence will mingle with the sacred violence of
the rites, turning the latter into a scandalous accomplice in the
process of pollution, even a kind of catalyst in the propagation of
further impurity" (1972, 39). I suspect this is the issue underlying the
two tales in which Saul disappoints his patron Samuel (1 Samuel 13:5-15;
15:1-35). For Saul, his hands full of Philistine blood, to have taken on
himself the task of offering priestly sacrifice was to trespass the
boundary between profane and holy violence. It was for the same reason
that Yahve would later forbid the red-handed David to build his temple
(1 Chronicles 22:8, a priestly redactional development of 1 Kings 5:3,
where David had simply not had time during his busy battle schedule to
build the temple). And when Saul had offered all the Amalekites as human
sacrifices to Yahve, thus fulfilling a duty of sacred violence, he yet
spared the life of King Agag, presumably to use as some sort of
diplomatic ace in the hole, and gave the captured livestock to his men.
Samuel was displeased because all alike should have been offered up. To
make exceptions out of worldly considerations was to compromise the
purely sacred character of the violence. One may imagine poor Agag
following this theological debate with keen interest, though he probably
was disappointed with the outcome.
Do we see anything of the kind in the
Gospels? Indeed we do. At least presupposed in the Gospels is the fact
of quisling compromise between the temple authorities, especially the
High Priest (like the Russian Orthodox Patriarch appointed by the KGB)
and the Romans/Herods (Horsley, 3-15). The hypocrisy did not escape the
people. Like the priests of Matthew 27:6-7 who piously scruple over
whether ritually impure bounty money may go back into the temple
treasury or should go for a charitable secular contribution, the temple
authorities strained out a gnat and swallowed a camel when they took
care to exclude heathen denarii from the temple while getting in bed
with Caesar and his flunkies to keep their privileged position. Again we
may imagine the disgust of Jesus in the "render unto Caesar" scene. The
confusion between sacred and profane violence in the temple finally led
to the cutting off of the sacrifice for Caesar at the hands of the
anti-priestly Jewish rebels, signaling the ruinous war with Rome.
Likewise, the story of Jesus' "cleansing of the temple" must be seen (or
at least Girard would surely see it) in the context of impending
sacrificial crisis.
The root problem in a time of
sacrificial crisis is the breaking down of traditional class, gender,
race, and social boundaries. We witness the same sort of thing today in
the fundamentalist panic over Gay rights, women's equality, and even the
theory of evolution which seems to them to erode the wall between
animals and humans. Every culture is defined by where it draws its
lines. And when the lines start to be erased, there is going to be
trouble, including vigilante violence. When people lose confidence in
the proper channels for mediating violence, when, as in our society,
they feel the justice system coddles criminal who should really be
executed (thus expunging the difference between innocent and guilty),
then people begin to take the law into their own hands, and chaos
erupts. If the proper channels for violence are sacrificial and ritual
in character, then the breakdown or compromise of this system will
result in chaos as we have just seen. "The primitive mind... has no
difficulty imagining an affiliation between violence and
nondifferentiation and, indeed, is often obsessed by the possible
consequences of such a union. Natural differences are conceived in terms
of cultural differences, and vice versa... Because there is no real
difference between the various modes of differentiation, there is in
consequence no difference between the manner in which things fail to
differ; the disappearance of natural differences can thus bring to mind
the dissolution of regulations pertaining to the individual's proper
place in society-that is, can instigate a sacrificial crisis" (Girard
1972, 56).
We see something of this erosion of
traditional differences in the Gospels, too. But the interesting thing
is that Jesus himself is depicted as the chief culprit in erasing those
lines! If we take seriously recent work by Schüssler Fiorenza, Crossan,
Werner Kelber and others, Jesus appears to have proclaimed a
"discipleship of equals" between men and women, welcomed the
Untouchables as Gandhi did, received despised Gentiles into fellowship,
accepted tax collectors and associated with sinners to the puzzlement of
the traditionally pious. Sanders even doubts that Jesus really asked any
of these people to repent. Jesus, as painted by Schüssler Fiorenza,
Horsley, Crossan and others, even sought to abolish the patriarchal
family (Matthew 10:34-36; 23:9). Hamerton-Kelly finds in Mark an idyllic
picture of "the confraternity of the kingdom. Within this new context,
the traditional family is an anachronism. The new radical fatherhood of
God relativizes the claims of earthly parents and family obligations,
which were in any case organized for the most part according to the
forms of sacred violence" (1994, 83).
While this whole raft of politically
correct exegeses might be challenged, a greater problem in attributing
such notions to the historical Jesus is that saying after relevant
saying has long ago been shown to be a redactional composition or a
community formation. Horsley in particular seems fully as credulous
about the accuracy of the Gospels as Girard himself. But let us suppose
the exegeses of the passages are correct, though their attribution to
Jesus is not. What we are left with is a collection of socially
disruptive sayings falsely ascribed to Jesus so as to pin the blame for
the current social-sacrificial crisis squarely upon him! Here think also
of the impression given in the Gospels that Jesus single-handedly
sparked the temple crisis. Neither the sacrificial program of Jesus
educed by Chilton nor the socio-political background of priestly
compromise reconstructed by Horsley is given explicitly in the Gospel
texts. Why not? The larger social conditions have been mythically
transformed, wider problems attributed to one man alone: the scapegoat.
Up to this point I have been willing
to grant for the sake of argument that Girard is correct in seeing Jesus
portrayed as unambiguously innocent in the Gospel accounts. Even if that
were so, we need simply conclude that the Gospels represent an advanced
stage of morally dualistic rewriting of the earlier version of the
scapegoat myth. "I implied that an original 'criminal' Baldr must have
existed in a more primitive version of the myth" (Girard, 1982, 79). I
suggest that, in Girardian terms, the revolutionary rhetoric of Jesus in
the Gospels constitutes surviving vestiges of the earlier version of the
Passion tale in which there was a "criminal" Jesus. Think also of the
discomfort of the various evangelists over what to do with the "false"
charge that Jesus had threatened to destroy the temple (Mark 14:57-59;
Matthew 26:59-61; Acts 6:12-14; John 2:18-22). John in particular makes
it clear his exonerating rationalization occurred to him long after the
fact, a perfect example of Girard's retroactive rehabilitation of the
criminal scapegoat.
Can Jesus really have been
single-handedly responsible for the sacrificial crisis of his day? Not
likely. Girard's explanation of the Oedipus myth fits just as nicely
here: "If the crisis has dropped from sight, if universal reciprocity
[of violence] is eliminated, it is because of the unequal distribution
of the very real parts of the crisis. In fact, nothing has been truly
abolished, nothing added, but everything has been misplaced. The
whole process of mythical formulation leads to a transferal of violent
undifferentiation from all the Thebans to the person of Oedipus. Oedipus
becomes the repository of all the community's ills. In the myth, the
fearful transgression of a single individual is substituted for the
universal onslaught of reciprocal violence. Oedipus is responsible for
the ills that have befallen his people. He has become a prime example of
the human scapegoat" (1972, 77). So has Jesus. Girard ought to have seen
that.
I am He as You are He as You are Me and We are All Together
As we have seen, another major sign
of the rise of reciprocal violence to crisis proportions is the
appearance of doubles or twins. This is a term Girard employs in several
related ways. First, in the process of mimesis, when one individual
models herself upon another, the model and the imitator are mimetic
twins. Second, Girard speaks of the two sides of any struggle, whether
individual or collective, as doubles or mimetic twins, indicating that
any significant difference between the two has been lost. Reciprocal
violence levels the playing field till people may even forget what the
violence was all about. Third, in this process, or as the occasion of
this process, all traditional differentiations are lost, as we have
seen. In this case everyone has become everyone else's twin or double.
In fact, since everyone, like Hawthorne's Young Goodman Brown, has come
to see the fiend in every face, everyone has become everyone else's
"monstrous double." Fourth, often this sort of collective doubling will
appear in myths reduced symbolically to a pair of matched characters,
usually antagonistic brothers or twins.
Fifth, once the mass settles on a
hapless victim to serve as its scapegoat, this unfortunate becomes the
blotter to soak up everyone's guilt and paranoia, and he or she becomes
the monstrous double of the society. This is the first act of
transference. With the second act, the scapegoat is sanctified and
idealized as a savior. But what is to be done with the guilt previously
attributed to him? Sixth, it is projected onto a secondary scapegoat. If
this happens, then we may speak of the new scapegoat as the monstrous
double of the first, rehabilitated scapegoat. Given the return of
dualist moralism after the crisis subsides, the scapegoat is thus
bifurcated, and his evil twin may be a second scapegoated individual (or
group: Jews, according to both Mack and Maccoby) or a mythic creation
(adding Loki alongside Hother).
I want to focus here on the
appearance in the Gospels of matched/opposing pairs of characters whose
function is to symbolize and concretize the mimetic doubling of the
larger society in the real crisis the myth reflects, the fourth use of
the doubles metaphor. Evident literary doubles of Jesus include John the
Baptist and Lazarus, but I must leave them aside here. I will consider
Simon Peter as a double of Jesus, then Judas Iscariot as another.
Girard is quick to note it when pairs
of mimetic twins in a myth have equivalent names or different versions
of the same name. In the Passion of John the Baptist, every named
character save for the baptizer himself is named Herod: Herod Antipas,
Herodias, and (implicitly) Herod, the brother from whom Herod Antipas
had wooed away Herodias. Similarly, Romulus and Remus are variants of
the same name. We might also think of the punning resemblance between
Jacob and the name of the river whose resident god he wrestles, the
Jabbock. And the rivals Evodia ("Successful") and Syntyche ("Lucky") in
Philippians 4:2-3, who are to be reconciled with the help of none other
than Syzygus ("Yokefellow")! Maccoby explains why in such cases the
names indicate the splitting of an originally single character. As the
various transferences and bifurcations occur during the evolution of the
myth, traits and functions of the original character come to be
multiplied or substituted. There are too many actantial roles for a
single character to play any more. So the character is multiplied, all
keeping the same name as a vestige of their original identity (1982,
126-130).
Simon Peter, Jesus' number one
disciple, might, seen through Girardian lenses, betray a considerable
resemblance to Simon the brother of Jesus mentioned in Mark 6:3. Though
it is possible that this list of names once functioned like the list of
the Twelve in Mark 3:14-19, i.e., as an official list of the
authoritative Heirs of Jesus, it is difficult to see much reason for
mentioning them by name--unless someone has passed along a fossilized
hint of Simon being Jesus' mimetic twin. He functions in the Gospels as
a sounding board to amplify Jesus' teachings, since, like Holmes's
Doctor Watson, he asks Jesus the question the readers are asking. Thus
he is a narrative commentary on the sayings of Jesus (the same point is
made in the doctrines of extremist Ismail'is who see Jesus and Peter as
distinct syzygies emanated from Allah, Jesus being the "proclaimer" of
an exoteric revelation, Peter being the "foundation" who explains the
esoteric aspect of the teaching afterward.
More than this, however, Simon Peter
seems to be the externalized voice of Jesus' own indecision and doubt.
When at Caesarea Philippi Simon voices his opposition to the plan of
Jesus' coming death, do we not catch the hint that he has struck a
nerve? Jesus turns on him with curses because he himself is thinking the
very same thing and is trying to resist the temptation. This is exactly
what we see later in the Garden of Gethsemane when Jesus voices overt
doubts: if at all possible, cannot Jesus avoid the hemlock cup? Of
course Jesus does emerge from the Garden with his resolve intact. He
will go the way of the cross in any case. And Simon embodies this, too.
For he is also Simon of Cyrene, who carries the cross of Jesus.
And he is Simon the Zealot. Bearing
in mind that in the Greek text a "zealous one" and a "jealous one" are
the same word, we can see another sign of Peter as a mimetic
counterpart of Jesus. We have already seen this in the scene of Peter's
confession (where the affirmation of Jesus' identity may thus denote
Jesus' own realization of his identity) and its aftermath in
which Jesus rebukes his own doubt, calling it Satan. We ought also to
remember the Last Supper at which Peter accepts that Jesus will have to
die but swears he will see him through to the end, his own death as well
as Jesus'--for the two are the same. When Jesus questions Peter's
ironclad fidelity, is he again questioning his own? But in Girard's
terms, does Peter's protest of loyalty denote that Peter has sought to
adopt as his own the destiny of his model? In fact, Peter does die by
crucifixion in early Christian tradition (beginning with John 21:18-19).
Drawing on Basilides' redaction of the myth, we might say that Simon (as
Simon of Cyrene) not only shares the fate of his Lord but supplants it,
actually taking Jesus' place on the cross. Another set of brothers,
James and John, want to mimetically appropriate the destiny of Jesus,
too (Mark 10:35-41).
Simon Peter will meet his own double
later on in the form of the anti-Simon, Simon Magus, who approaches
Peter about and asks to duplicate his powers of transmitting the Spirit
(Acts 8:18-24). There are still more counterparts to Simon Peter, but we
must wait till later to meet them.
Judas Goat
Judas is surely the most complex of
Jesus' doubles. We have already noted that he plays the role of the
secondary scapegoat once Jesus has been retroactively exonerated.
Maccoby develops the idea independently of Girard, though he says
precisely what Girard ought to have said on the subject. Maccoby cites
numerous myths in which the executioner of the hero is the hero's
brother (e.g., Cain and Abel). The point of such a symbol is to
bifurcate the original victim so that the executioner may be seen to
bear away the evil originally attached to the victim. The original
scapegoat has been split into two, one going to Yahve, the other to
Azazel (Maccoby, 1982, 128). Though Girard cannot bring himself to apply
it to Jesus and Judas, he is aware of the same trajectory of mythic
evolution: "Similarly, the Aztec god Xipe-Totec demonstrates the ability
of the incarnation of the sacred to assume different roles in the
system. Sometimes this god is killed and flayed in the person of a
victim offered as substitute for him; at other times the god becomes the
executioner, flaying victims in order to don their skin. Evidently
religious thought perceives all those who participate in this violent
interplay, whether actively or passively, as doubles" (1972, 251).
In light of these analyses we can
plot out the trajectory of the "Big Bang" that led to the multiplication
of Judas figures. Judas is of course the Iscariot, the False One, the
Betrayer. (Here I must side with Bertil Gärtner against Maccoby, who
rejects this interpretation in favor of "the Sicarius." Gärtner
passim; Maccoby, 1992, 135). He is the sacred executioner. But to
play this role to the fullest, he should be Jesus' brother, too, and he
is. He is the Judas numbered among Jesus' siblings in Mark 6:3. More
specifically, he is even a twin brother, Didymus Judas Thomas,
Judas the Twin. And of course Judas must be one of the disciples as
well, in order to be within striking distance when the moment comes.
But as Luke knew (and as Schmithals
and Günter Klein knew even better), there remains a problem counting out
one of the Twelve if there is to be a subsequent college of twelve
apostles. How can they all have been appointed by the Risen Jesus (1
Corinthians 15:5) if one of them had already hanged himself? Judas was
simply bifurcated into "Judas Iscariot" and "Judas not Iscariot" (John
14:22). A few manuscripts omit "not" in John 14:22. If this should
chance to be the original reading, suppressed by harmonizing scribes for
obvious reasons, then here we would actually be witnessing a stage in
the ongoing doubling of Judas. Perhaps the two resultant Judases counted
as numbers twelve and thirteen, with Thaddaeus as one of the first
eleven. But later, somehow Thaddaeus was assimilated to Judas not
Iscariot. This left the famous gap, which Lebbaeus and Nathaniel might
have been attempts to fill. Speaking of odd manuscripts, a few have the
reading "Judas the Zealot" at Matthew 10:3 (in some Old Latin
manuscripts) and at John 14:22 (in some Sahidic manuscripts). This, too,
would be significant in the same way "Simon the Zealot" was, the epithet
indicating, for neo-Girardian exegesis at any rate, mimetic rivalry:
Judas the Jealous.
If twins are literary/mythic
personifications of the mimetic doubling in periods of
sacrificial/social crisis, Girard observes, the scapegoat (the monstrous
double of society as a whole) can just as well be a product of or a
partner in incest, just like Oedipus. It is an equivalent image for the
horrific effacing of differences and boundaries. We see the logic of the
mytheme spinning itself out in the growth of the Judas tradition. Late
in the megatext, in The Golden Legend, we find Judas married to
his mother (Kermode, 95), having killed his father (Maccoby, 1992, 106),
just like Oedipus, and for the same reason. In the thirteenth-century
Ballad of Judas he is living incestuously with his sister (Maccoby,
1992, 107).
And if Judas is the "monstrous
double" of Jesus, we might take a second look at the intriguing guess of
some exegetes that the epithet "Son of Perdition" in John 17:12 means
the same thing it does in 2 Thessalonians 2:3. This makes Judas the
Antichrist, surely the monstrous double of Jesus! Finally, as a mimetic
twin of Jesus, he might be expected to seek the same fate as Jesus. And
he gets it. As Maccoby points out, not only does Judas die hanging from
a tree like Jesus (Matthew 27:5), but if one factors in Luke's variant
in Acts 1: 18-19, where Judas' manner of death is left vague but
involves a rain of his blood soaking into the ground, we can hear an
echo of the underlying myth on which Jesus' crucifixion was built: the
sacrificial deaths of Attis, Abel, (and, one might add, Baal) to
fertilize the ground with their blood. (This mytheme is still faintly
visible in John 19:41a, "Now in the place where he was crucified there
was a garden.") Thus it was not only guilt but tell-tale mythic coloring
that was transferred to Judas the Twin. Could it be that Luke's and
Matthew's versions of the death of Judas differ because each has tried
in his own way to break the parallel between Jesus and Judas, Luke
omitting the hanging (=crucifixion) element but retaining the Field of
Blood as the place of death, while Matthew retained the hanging but
removed the death from the Field of Blood by substituting a different
account, cobbled together from readings of two versions of Zechariah
11:13, and with it a different, and safer, etymology?
Some traditions report that it was
Judas who died on the cross in Jesus' stead, having been miraculously
transformed into his likeness. Abu Ja'far al-Tabari (died 923 C.E.)
quoted Ibn Ishaq as relating how "Some of the Christians allege that it
was Judas Iscariot who was made [Jesus'] semblance to them and that they
crucified him despite his saying, 'I am not one of his companions! I am
the one who pointed him out to you!'" (Robinson, 131). It is striking
that such Christian docetism survived long enough in remote areas for
Muhammad to have picked it up from Christians when they converted to
Islam. And so here is a Christian tradition according to which Judas'
mimetic rivalry with his Lord came to an ironic fruition. The point is
actually rather important. The choice of the scapegoat by the mob is
usually random, much like the picking of Simon of Cyrene out of the
crowd to carry Jesus' cross (and think again of Basilides' reading:
Simon had been picked at random to be crucified!). It could be
anybody because in the crisis of reciprocal violence none is
particularly more guilty or innocent than anyone else; indeed, these
terms have for the time being lost their meaning. The scapegoat is,
however, still falsely accused since he cannot be totally and
uniquely responsible as charged. But it could as easily be anybody.
And this means it could just as
easily have been Judas as Jesus! This is another implication of their
being mimetic twins. Girard makes this point in discussing the Oedipus
story. Oedipus has concluded that the plague in Thebes is a divine
judgment for the murder of Laius, his predecessor on the throne. The
task is now to smoke out the regicide and punish him. Of course Oedipus
himself is eventually disclosed as the murderer, albeit an unwitting
one. But, says Girard, this identification of Oedipus as the culprit was
not inevitable, at least not in whatever real set of events the story
reflects. The blame for the death circled like a vulture for a while.
Initially Oedipus tried to pin the blame on Tiresias and Creon, but he
couldn't make it stick. They returned the blame to him, and they did
manage to make it stick. Did Oedipus "in fact" commit the deed? He
himself is willing to admit he did, but this only means he allowed
himself to be persuaded of their version of events. He knew he killed
some old man, but at the moment he did not know his identity. It may or
may not have been Laius: who knows? But the tail has finally been pinned
on the donkey, and that's where it will stay. Oedipus is elected as the
scapegoat to save Thebes. "Having oscillated freely among the three
protagonists, the full burden of guilt finally settles on one. It might
very well have settled on another, or on none... The attribution of
guilt that henceforth passes for 'true' differs in no way from those
attributions that will henceforth be regarded as 'false,' except that in
the case of the 'true' guilt no voice is raised to protest any aspect of
the charge. A particular version of events succeeds in imposing itself;
it loses its polemical nature in becoming the acknowledged basis of the
myth, in becoming the myth itself" (1972, 78). Judas is forever vilified
as a thief (John 12:6), but remember that Jesus was numbered among the
thieves (Mark 14:48;15:27), too. And if Judas was called demon-possessed
(John 13:27; Luke 22:3), so was Jesus (John 8:48). Neither set of
invectives counts as any more than that. One stuck, the other didn't. Or
should we not say, the charges stuck first to Jesus, the primary
scapegoat, then were reapplied to Judas, the secondary scapegoat.
To take it one step further, the
supposed possession of Judas by Satan may be seen as yet another
distancing device to shift some measure of the blame from Judas as the
sacred executioner. "The condition called 'possession' is in fact
but one particular interpretation of the monstrous double... Some
presence seems to be acting through him-a god, a monster, or
whatever creature is in the process of investing his body" (Girard,
1972, 165). Thus Satan becomes the monstrous double of Judas, and a
tertiary scapegoat in his behalf. In the Coptic fragments of the
Gospel of Bartholomew we read that it was Judas' nagging wife who
put him up to his mischief (Maccoby, 1992, 91).
It only remains to tie up a
surprising loose end. If the panicky words of Judas quoted by Ibn Ishaq
("I am not one of his companions!") should remind one of Peter's denials
(Mark 14:66-71), this may be no accident, because Peter and Judas would
seem to be doubles of one another, too. If Judas Iscariot is Judas the
Zealot, and if Simon Peter is Simon the Zealot; if Judas is one of the
brothers of Jesus, and if Simon is another, then we might take another
look at the epithet "Judas of Simon Iscariot" (John 13:2), which could
as easily denote "Judas, brother of Simon" as "Judas, son of Simon" (Maccoby,
1992, 134-135). But Simon Peter the False One? Peter Iscariot? That
would aptly describe the cowardly denier of Mark 14:66-71 who afterwards
breaks into weeping just as Judas afterward repented (Matthew 27:3). And
compare John 6:66-71 with Mark 8:27-33. In Peter van Greenaway's novel
The Judas Gospel (1972), a secret Dead Sea Scroll, a Testament
of Judas, reveals that it was Peter, not Judas, who sold Jesus out,
and that Peter successfully framed Judas for the deed. Is that possible?
Was Peter, like Hother, a secondary scapegoat later replaced by Judas,
a tertiary scapegoat (like Loki)?
Partners in Mime
Judas and Simon Peter may be the most
obvious cases of mimetic twins among the disciples, but the Gospels do
not hesitate to cast the whole group of them in the role. Almost like a
Greek chorus, the disciples often speak as one with the voice of mimetic
desire. They are forever squabbling over who is the greatest, or will be
the greatest. And they pin their hopes of greatness on the coat tails of
Jesus ("If only I can touch the hem of his garment...!"). They
generously leave the central throne for Jesus but bicker over the seats
of honor alongside him. Mark pictures them always dumbfounded, rebuked
for misunderstanding just when they thought they'd got it straight. It
all fits Girard's framework perfectly. The mimetic double seeks to be
just like his model, but as he closes in, the model tries to keep some
distance, sets up some obstacle. "A disciple is not above his teacher,
nor a slave above his master; it is enough for a disciple to be like his
teacher, and the slave like his master" (Matthew 10:24-25a). "Are you
able to drink the cup that I drink, or to be baptized with the baptism
with which I am baptized?" (Mark 10:38). And see 2 Kings 4:11-37; Mark
9:14-29, and various tales of Aesclepius, Asclepiades, and Pancrates
where the disciples prove utterly incapable of mimicking the feats of
the master. Or think of Joshua who first says to the people, "Therefore
fear Yahve, and serve him in sincerity and in faithfulness" (Joshua
24:14) and then casts this in their teeth: "You cannot serve Yahve, for
he is a holy god; he is a jealous god; he will not forgive your
transgressions or your sins!" (Joshua 24:19). The puzzled disciple finds
himself in a double bind (Girard, 1972, 179; Adolf Holl, Jesus in
Bad Company, 1972, 48-49, shrewdly points out, following Scheler,
how Christians have inherited the same predicament. They worship a Jesus
who made ethical demands they cannot follow, not being a god like him!
Thus Jesus appears to have borne away not only our sins, but our
righteousness as well.).
Increasingly frustrated, the imitator
gradually slips from adoration of the model into a love-hate
relationship with the model, who is increasingly perceived as a
competitor and an obstacle, until unalloyed hatred finally emerges. "By
a strange but explicable consequence of their relationship, neither the
model nor the disciple is disposed to acknowledge the inevitable
rivalry. The model, even when he has openly encouraged imitation ["If
any one would come after me, let him take up his cross and follow me."],
is surprised to find himself engaged in competition. He concludes that
the disciple has betrayed his confidence by following in his footsteps.
As for the disciple, he feels both dejected and humiliated, judged
unworthy by his model of participating in the superior existence the
model himself enjoys" (Girard, 1972, 146). "Depart from me, O Lord, for
I am a sinful man."
"Conflictual mimesis will inevitably
unify by leading two or more individuals to converge on one and the same
adversary that all wish to strike down" (Girard, 1978, 26). The
disciples of Jesus have been imitators of Jesus and thus rivals of one
another, and as Jesus continues to frustrate them, what is their next
step going to be? Girard should expect them to unite against him. No
more bickering about who is to be greatest! We will not have this man to
reign over us! They share harmonious fellowship once again as they
jointly devour the flesh and blood of their erstwhile master, their
scapegoat, the lamb of God who took away their sins. Theodore J. Weeden
(Mark: Traditions in Conflict, 1971) argued that Mark portrays
the disciples finally becoming the enemies of Jesus, betraying, denying,
abandoning him, not even visiting his tomb. I believe that a neo-Girardian
scrutiny of the Passion will make that description seem mild indeed. In
what follows I will attempt to show how Girard's methods should disclose
an earlier version in which it was none other than the disciples of
Jesus who conspired to kill him. Of course, Girard himself would rend
his garments in outraged horror at the suggestion. It is my suggestion,
based on his method. So the hands are the hands of Girard, but the voice
is the voice of Price.
We Esteemed Him Smitten of God
Sifting through the mosaic tiles of
the Passion narratives, I believe the neo-Girardian investigator would
have to conclude that it was the anointing in Bethany that proved to be
the back-breaking straw. Here the disciples first recognized their
idol's clay feet. A shocking lapse convinced them that they held more
firmly to his radical ethos than he himself did. "It doesn't help us if
you're inconsistent. They only need a small excuse to put us all away!"
(Judas in Jesus Christ Superstar). The inconsistency? With the
inflexible pedantry of the small-minded zealot, "some" (Mark 14:4) on
the scene objected to the waste of the fancy oil: "Why was the ointment
thus wasted? For this ointment might have been sold for more than three
hundred denarii, and [the proceeds] given to the poor" (Mark 14:4b-5).
Isn't this the very policy Jesus had urged on so many others? The issue
is not quite that they were being holier than Jesus; rather, they were
being more like Jesus than Jesus! And consider the resultant double
bind. Jesus has been caught out. This discovery convinces them that they
are better than Jesus in living out his ethic. Mimesis seems to have
gained its object! But in the same moment, they must mourn the loss of
their idol. As their idol has proven to be less than perfect, their
victory is cheapened by the knowledge that they have only surpassed
someone who was really no better than them all along! And so how far
have they come? They scorn the model not only for disappointing them but
also for depriving them of the goal they thought they had been pursuing
and finally gained.
But can we be so certain that those
objecting from the peanut gallery were disciples? That was apparently
Matthew's inference, since his version has "the disciples" as the
carpers (26:8). Who else would likely have been present on the scene?
Besides, in Mark 6:37, the miraculous feeding, it is also the disciples
who speak indignantly about giving something worth great amounts of
denarii to the hungry.
It could be that the identity of the
critics was known to Mark but that he suppressed it, implying that Judas
was the only disciple to take umbrage, since it is he who directly goes
to the priests to make his offer. Matthew leaves the disciples as the
culprits, but he has tried to soften the blow in another way. Jesus'
host on the occasion, according to some source at Matthew's disposal,
was one "Simon the leper." By now our Girardian instincts are
sufficiently honed to detect here another version of Simon Peter. It is
Simon Peter's house. Why disguise him as a leper? Such an identification
serves no apparent narrative purpose--unless we are being subtly
directed to Numbers 12:1-15, a story in which Miriam and Aaron dare to
criticize Moses on account of a woman, his Cushite bride. For her
meddling, Miriam is turned into a leper. Is Simon made a leper by
Matthew because he dared criticize Jesus on account of a woman? I
wouldn't be surprised.
Luke has concealed Simon Peter's
identity under a different mask. He has made him into Simon the Pharisee
(Luke 7:36-40ff). Exegetes have noted that this would be the single
instance of Jesus addressing a Pharisee or other outsider by name. And
yet he elsewhere calls Simon Peter by name (e.g., Luke 22:31; Matthew
16:17; 17:25). While no evangelist minds very much having Jesus rebuke
Peter, this time Luke feels things have gone too far: Simon has
seemingly lost his faith in Jesus altogether. "If this man were a
prophet..." So it must be some other Simon. That's the ticket.
It is by no means difficult to see
how the disciples might have taken offense at Jesus' saying "You always
have the poor with you, and whenever you will, you can do good to them;
but you will not always have me" (Mark 14:7). The heartless arrogance of
this saying has always troubled pious readers, all the way back to the
late-first, early-second century, when the Didache warned its
readers to eject as a false prophet any itinerant who said under divine
afflatus, "Give me money," which is pretty much the same sentiment. The
Mark 14:7 saying is only the caption of the scene of extravagant
anointing. The actions spoke just as loudly. Note that Luke has clumsily
tried to change the subject, redirecting the reader's attention to the
supposed bad character of the woman. It becomes an incoherent mishmash
of themes from other tales in which Jesus forgives sins. As Girard says,
"The only feasible or even conceivable response seems to be that the
version of the myth we are analyzing is not the first" (1982,
68). My Girardian guess is that after this incident, it is not Judas
alone who moves to engineer the death of Jesus, but his apostolic
compatriots as well.
Scapegoats Gruff
I would next like to deal with a set
of four pericopae which seem perhaps to reflect scapegoat themes, though
they do not bear directly on Jesus as the scapegoat. What are they doing
here? Perhaps, as elsewhere in the gospels, it was simply a vague but
discernible kinship of theme which accounted for them being included in
the general vicinity of Jesus' own Passion.
The first episode is that of blind
Bartimaeus (Mark 10:46-52). Once we see a crowd menacing a blind beggar,
a doubly good choice for a scapegoat, and the beggar calling out for
mercy, we know the game is afoot. Who knows but that originally the
story told not of the recovery of Bartimaeus' sight, but rather his
narrow escape from an angry mob? Like the man in the Garden who just
managed to escape by the skin of his teeth, glad enough to leave his
only garment behind, given the alternative, Bartimaeus pitches aside the
superfluous ballast of his threadbare coat to run for his life.
We must cast our net wide: could it
be that the similar story of Jesus' healing a blind man outside of
Bethsaida (Mark 8:22-26) was another version of the Bartimaeus tale?
"And some people brought to him a blind man." That has an ominous ring
about it, reminiscent of the pariah pericope John 7:53-8:11, that of
the woman taken in adultery. "The Pharisees brought a woman who had been
caught in adultery." They meant to carry her out dead. Is the blind man
of Bethsaida being scapegoated, too? If so, somehow he gets off the
hook, but Jesus tells him not to take any chances: "Do not even enter
the village."
The second adjacent scapegoat episode
is Matthew 21:18-20, the cursing of the fig tree, along with 21:33-39,
the parable of the wicked tenants. It only takes a wee bit of
reshuffling to make the parable a story in which strife breaks out among
the share croppers themselves, who then gang up on a figure marginally
associated with the vineyard. The man they kill does not work there but
is the son of the absentee landlord. His death puts an end to their
strife. He is driven outside the gates to be killed, like the ancient
Greek pharmakos, or, following Mark 12:8, he is killed and then
cast forth. And if we add the story of the fig tree, we might even
detect a trace of some earlier version of Jesus' own death in which he
was blamed for a wasting agricultural disease a la Joel 1:11-15, where
vinedressers and withered fig trees are mentioned in the same breath.
Next we may briefly consider
Matthew's parable of the guest without a wedding garment (22:2,11-14).
Before the rejoicing of the wedding feast could begin in earnest, had
there once been a need to choose someone for a scapegoat, in this case
marked out by his poor dress? If so, it would be a reflection of the
marriage festival custom of the Niquas in which the marriage is sealed
by the scars won by relatives of the bride and groom in a battle during
the ceremony. Often the ritual violence culminates in the pre-arranged
death of a slave during the general melee. The slave is a perfect
scapegoat to banish the inter-familial tensions since he is helpless and
will have no one to avenge his murder (Girard, 1972, 248). Neither did
the poor man in Matthew 22, who no doubt wondered why he had been
hustled in at the last moment at all. He found out the hard way.
Finally, there is the conundrum put
to Jesus by the Sadducees in Matthew 22:23-33, the parable of the woman
with seven husbands, if I may venture to call it that. Girardian
exegesis, it seems to me, ought to grow suspicious at the picture of the
woman surviving when all seven husbands have come to a bad end in rapid
succession. Is she Lady Bluebeard? Perhaps the shroud is on the wrong
corpse here. We might speculate that in an earlier version, the seven
husbands were all very much alive, and it is the death of the woman
which is at issue. Instead of bringing this riddle to Jesus, suppose in
the original version, it was the woman herself who was brought--by the
seven men. Suddenly we are dealing with something that sounds remarkably
like the adulteress pericope again. Shrewd popular exegesis long ago
suggested that no one took Jesus up on his invitation to cast the first
stone, provided one was sinless--because all of them had sinned with
her! Plug in here, if you will, the interchange between Jesus and a very
similar character in John 4:16-18, "'Go call your husband and return
here.' The woman answered him, 'I have no husband.' Jesus said to her,
'You are right to say, "I have no husband." The fact is, you have had
five husbands, and the man you have now is not your husband.'" Perhaps
these previous "husbands" were someone else's husbands. Perhaps
the seven "husbands" of the woman in Matthew 22 were not that woman's
husbands either. As in the "cast the first stone" pericope, perhaps the
group of seven had come to resent one another for their common dalliance
with her. The only way to heal the breach between the rivals was to
eliminate that which stood between them: her. Just as Girard was able to
corroborate his reversal of the myth of the Curetes and baby Zeus (that
originally they conspired to destroy him, not to protect him) by
comparing it with a surviving parallel in which the Titans do gang up on
an infant god to kill him, I have tried to reconstruct an original
scapegoat version of the woman with seven husbands by comparing it with
the related story of the woman taken in adultery.
You're Entitled to One Last Meal
As to the Last Supper, we can
dispense with two notable but fairly simple items quickly. The first is
the Words of Institution. It is clear enough, on any critical reading,
that here we are dealing with a ceremonial etiology. As Loisy noted long
ago, the very words "This is my body, this is my blood" imply a ritual
context in which a celebrant explains the meaning of the various items
of the liturgy. The case is not entirely closed, as witness Chilton's
discussion in The Temple of Jesus (150-154), but I would see the
words as part of a post-Jesus liturgy. The question then becomes, what
was the sacrificial violence that first gave rise to this masked
liturgical commemoration? Here the veil is rather thin: it is the death
of Jesus. But note that it must be the death of Jesus as a collective
murder, only later sanctified as a sacrificial ritual. The key is the
added word, "Drink ye all of it." Girard explains, "The sacrificial
ceremony requires a show of collective participation, if only in purely
symbolic form. This association of the collectivity with the sacrificial
victim is found in numerous instances-notably in the Dionysiac
sparagmos... All the participants, without exception, are required
to take part in the death scene" (1972, 100). The reason, even if no
longer understood, is to reflect the logic of the original mob lynching.
The entire group must take part, or the violence will remain on the
level of "bad," i.e., secular and personal, violence. In concrete terms,
a murder in which only some participate would leave itself open for
vendetta against the individual killers and their families. But if the
whole collectivity has taken part in it, what are you going to do?
Vengeance is short circuited, and peace returns. The direction for all
present at the eucharist to commune echoes the unity of the disciples in
their murder of Jesus. This may sound far-fetched, but as Maccoby says
(1992, 94) it remains true today that Christians are quite happy for
Jesus to have died, no matter how much they may mourn the same event.
But that is the whole logic of the scapegoat, isn't it?
In Luke's version of the Supper scene
he has Jesus quote Isaiah 53:12 (Luke 22:37), "he was reckoned among the
transgressors." Here is the tip of a large iceberg, the early Christian
use of the Deutero-Isaianic Servant Song. Let us simply note that one
could ask no better evidence, not that the Gospels expose and debunk the
scapegoat myth as Girard says, but just the reverse, that they embrace
it whole-heartedly. This application of Isaiah 53 to Jesus plainly
presupposes Christians looking back at the days when they ("we")
acted wrongly, albeit in good faith, thinking Jesus to be a villain
condemned by God. It was only later that they "realized" the savior had
been innocent all along, that it was the secret plan of God that he
should die to bear away the sins of his contemporaries. In the early
Christian singing of the Servant Song we see, as Girard should lead us
to expect, only the second transfer, that of guilt away from the
scapegoat and onto the community of faith who erred in ignorance. Of the
first transfer, the attribution of the community's ills to the scapegoat
as if they were his, we hear only echoes. Do they yet know that they
had victimized the innocent scapegoat by piling their sins high
on his back? No, they know only that they had been wrong in imagining
him to be suffering from his own sins. They believe it is only now,
retrospectively, that the vicarious dimension of his suffering
has become known. In other words, the scapegoating character of the act
of generative violence has been suppressed and is now safely forgotten.
The designation by Jesus of his
betrayer must occupy us next. We usually read John's account of Jesus
giving the sop to Judas in answer to the query of the Beloved Disciple
and Peter, as if Jesus already knew who would betray him and is telling
the secret in pantomime so as to prevent any disturbance. And that is no
doubt the Fourth Evangelist's intention. But Maccoby (1982, 125)
believes he can sniff out an earlier version in which Jesus engineered
being handed over to the authorities (much as in Kazantzakis's The
Last Temptation of Christ). In giving the sop to Judas he was making
the decision as to who would do the dirty work. While this suggestion is
attractive, I cannot help thinking that for Jesus to hand the sop to
Judas, implying that it was Jesus' own decision to make, represents a
redactional attempt to cover up an earlier version, still visible in
Mark 14:20 ("It is one of the twelve, one who is dipping bread into the
same dish with me") and Matthew 26:23 ("He who has dipped his hand in
the dish with me, will betray me"), in which Jesus had left it to
chance, much as in Acts 1:26, where the apostles cast lots to determine
Judas' replacement. (It is even possible that the Acts scene is a
rewritten version of the Last Supper scene.) Since chance, like God,
moves in mysterious ways, it is employed like Gideon's fleece to let God
express his will (cf. 1 Samuel 6:7-9). It is to open up a zone of
indeterminacy, breaking the link of human cause and effect, so that God
may have a window of intervention. "The victim is chosen by lot [whose]
expulsion will save the community" (Girard, 1972, 314).
But in Jesus' case it is not
precisely the victim who is chosen, but rather the sacred executioner. I
suggest, along Girardian lines, that the lot is being cast here (by a
method only disclosed afterward so as to prevent any attempt to
influence the outcome) in order to choose by divine providence who is
to make the choice of victim. Again, this would be needful to ensure
the victim was taken by surprise and could not flee forewarned, as he
could had the lot elected him there on the spot. But wasn't Jesus
already the chosen victim of the scheming twelve who were sick of him?
According to my reconstruction of the anointing scene, yes. But as
Girard is the first to admit, the same originary event leaves its traces
in many and various myths. As de Maupassant observed, it is difficult to
keep one's deceptions consistent with one another. And here in the
dipping in the dish scene I am wagering that what we have is another
version of the story in which mimetic rivalries have developed between
the disciples themselves as well as between them and Jesus. In all the
bickering over which was the greatest, one might as easily point to
James and John (Mark 10:41) as the lightning rods of controversy (Mark
3:17), and thus the best choices for elimination (Mark 10:39). But then
there was Peter with his tiresome claims to primacy. Best to cast out
some scorner so dissension would go out. At the very least it ought
to provide a deterrent to further arguing! People still remembered the
story of Korah (Numbers 16; Jude 11), after all, but maybe they needed a
reminder.
It turns out to be Jesus, as he
discovers too late in the Garden. "Friend, why have you come?" (Matthew
26:50). Oh. That's why. Perhaps Judas himself did not know until
that moment. "The one I kiss is the man; seize him" (Matthew 26:48). As
many exegetes have noticed over the years, it makes no sense at all to
suppose that the guards have come to arrest Jesus not knowing what he
looks like! The whole reason for the clandestine arrest is supposed to
be that Jesus is so popular that everyone knows him! Maccoby
takes this incongruity to denote the later and superfluous addition of
Judas to a scene in which originally he did not figure. Likely enough.
But it could also be that the authorities simply want to make an example
of someone, and the choice is up to Judas, who can make no choice
till the moment comes. When it does, he kisses Jesus, pretty much at
random, and the matter is settled.
Why then does the canonical version
have both the death of Jesus and the role of Judas in bringing it about
preordained, locked into a divine plan? "The original act of violence is
unique and spontaneous. Ritual sacrifices, however, are multiple,
endlessly repeated. All those aspects of the original act that had
escaped man's control--the choice of time and place, the selection of
the victim--are now premeditated and fixed by custom" (Girard, 1972,
102). In precisely the same way, the liturgical recitation of the
Passion of Jesus came to have a preordained character since everyone
already knew what happened, and this expectation entered the story
itself, making all the events part of a divine script, both within and
without the narrative world.
Messiahs by the Sackful
Medieval Muslim commentators on the
Passion of Jesus, which they understood in a docetic framework, had
their own clever explanation as to why Judas had to tell the guards
which of these men was the notorious Jesus. As soon as Judas and his
goon squad arrived, Allah transformed all the disciples into the
physical likeness of Jesus! Thus the need to ask, "Will the real Jesus
please stand up?" In the confusion, Jesus himself ascended into heaven,
leaving only a choice among counterfeits. And it was one of them, in
some versions Judas himself, who wound up on the cross (Robertson, 127).
What is interesting about this version from a Girardian standpoint is
that it provides an unparalleled example of the mythic concretization of
mimetic doubles into literal, physical doubles, and on a large scale.
"If violence is a great leveler of men and everybody becomes the double,
or 'twin,' of his antagonist, it seems to follow that all the all the
doubles are identical and that any one can at any given moment become
the double of all the others" (Girard, 1972, 79). "According to Freud,
the crowd of doubles stands in absolute opposition to the absolute
specificity of the hero" (Girard, 1972, 203), but Girard would modify
this sketch at a significant point: the hero (actually, the victim)
stands opposed to a crowd of doubles who are his own doubles as
well, since in the crisis of reciprocal violence, all distinguishing
marks have faded away. Girard prefers the formulation of Freud according
to which we have "'A crowd of people all with the same name and
similarly attired'" (Girard, 1972, 212). That is said strikingly well in
the Islamic version of the arrest.
The End is Just a Little Harder When Brought About by Friends
But let us hypothesize another
version of the arrest in the Garden in which no Judas figures. Judas,
after all, would have to be a later addition, as a secondary scapegoat
to shift the deicidal blame from the shoulders of the community as a
whole. Suppose there was an earlier account in which the disciples
simply turned on Jesus en masse, ambushing him as the Senators
did Julius Caesar. Here we must take our hint from Girard's comparison
of the Curetes myth with the myth of the infant Dionysus. The Curetes
appear in the extant version as a phalanx of armed warriors forming a
circle around the godling to protect him. But comparison with the
Dionysus myth, in which the Titans close around Dionysus and dismember
him, leads Girard to infer that originally the Curetes did the same. It
was only later that the story was cleaned up by the simple expedient of
making the Curetes Zeus' bodyguards instead of his assassins.
In the Gethsemane scene we have
similar elements. Jesus is with a crowd, his disciples, at least some of
whom are carrying weapons. Suddenly Jesus is menaced by a
weapon-brandishing crowd. The only ones actually said to employ any
weapons in the ensuing melee are Jesus' disciples. Jesus sees that
resistance is futile and allows himself to be led away peaceably, though
he is stung by the feeling of betrayal. Of course when we fill in
specific details as the evangelists do, we see that the armed disciples
only sought to protect Jesus from arrest by an invading second group.
But perhaps that is not the only way to fill in the blanks.
Surprisingly little would change if
the story were to be rewritten as that of Jesus' being ambushed and
apprehended by his own disciples. And as a neo-Girardian, I am
suggesting that the alteration went in the other direction. Attackers
have been converted into protectors. In Matthew, Mark, and John, there
is no preparation whatever for the sudden appearance of the disciples'
swords. Presumably this would have fit better a version in which the
weapons came as just as much a surprise to Jesus as to the reader. It
would make more sense, then, for Jesus to say to the "crowd" of
disciples, "Have you come out as against a robber, with swords and
clubs to capture me? Day after day I was with you in the temple
teaching, and you did not seize me" (Mark 14:49). Matthew (26:55) has
changed the crucial phrase to "Day after day I sat in the temple
teaching," which seems to mean merely "You knew where to find me."
Perhaps Matthew realized Mark's text could be read as meaning something
else, something he did not like.
If we picture the group of disciples
as the murderers of Jesus, as I believe consistent Girardian exegesis
would require, then must we write off the series of trials before the
Sanhedrin and Pilate as forming no part of the original? Not quite. As
for Jesus' trial (or hearing, or interrogation) before the Sanhedrin, it
bears clear marks of having been, not invented, but transformed. Most
likely, playing by Girardian rules, the group before whom Jesus is
brought is once again his own disciples. For one thing, this would at a
single stroke rid us of the vexing problem of the Sanhedrin holding a
capital trial on Passover eve, an incongruity that already has many
scholars willing to dismiss the whole scene as mud-slinging fiction
anyway.
Is the role of the chief villain
Caiaphas a complete fiction, too? Again, no. His priestly miter is on
the wrong head, though. His vestments do not quite fit their wearer, any
more than Saul's armor fit David. If we lift the turban from over the
concealed brows, we recognize a familiar face, for "Caiaphas," at least
here, is yet another double of "Cephas," Simon Peter, binding and
loosing as he sees fit. The "real" Peter, the Simon Peter persona, who
from the standpoint of a later piety cannot be imagined leading a
drumhead court marshal against the Christ, is nonetheless on the scene.
He has been moved from center stage, but not very far! We find him only
a few yards away, in the high priest's courtyard. But even there he is
an understudy, playing essentially the same role, only toned down. He is
still among the "wrong crowd," (and this much, of course, Girard does
see, in The Scapegoat, chapter 12). Eric Auerbach, in Mimesis,
urged us to draw the contrast between Jesus on trial inside and Peter on
trial (though in a lower court!) outside. But I am urging a comparison
between Caiaphas inside and Cephas outside. Just as Caiaphas condemns
Jesus to death, so does Cephas: "I do not know the man!" Do we not here
catch an echo of Jesus' own sentence of doom upon his enemies? "Depart
from me; ye cursed; I never knew you!"
John, trying to supply some narrative
verisimilitude, has Peter admitted to the priestly quarters by the
Beloved Disciple because the latter is known to the high priest. "It's
okay; he's with me." What on earth is going on here? Anyone is
going to have to strain pretty far to catch this fly ball! C.S.
Griffin even identified the Beloved Disciple as Judas himself (Judas
Iscariot, the Author of the Fourth Gospel, 1892, in Maccoby 1992,
138; also Kermode, 91-92)! That would certainly explain the Beloved
Disciple's chumminess with the powers that be. But through Girardian
lenses, we can spot another intriguing possibility. The detail of the
Beloved Disciple whispering to the bouncer is a vestige of the earlier
version in which this disciple, simply as a disciple, belonged to
the group before whom Jesus was being tried, because he was being
brought before the disciples!
Similarly, recall how Matthew and
John make Joseph of Arimathea a secret disciple of Jesus, John adding
Nicodemus to the list. Of course the two evangelists are trying to make
sense of what seems to them a contradiction: how could the man anxious
to see Jesus properly buried be a member of the group that condemned
him? But the incongruity arose only once that group was transformed from
the disciples into the Sanhedrin. According to the scapegoat theory, it
is quite natural that the crowd of murderers should come to take a more
sympathetic view of the scapegoat after his death, since his death did
heal their divisions. Joseph was another vestige of the stage when the
killers were the disciples. His name even recalls that of another famous
biblical scapegoat betrayed by his (nearly a) dozen brethren.
When Jesus is libeled by "false
witnesses" who claim they heard him threaten to destroy the temple, most
scholars already see something amiss. As noted above, this feature is
widely recognized as an attempt to defuse an apologetical bomb. To use
Crossan's felicitous term, it is "damage control." Jesus must have said
something of the kind, though Christians soon came to wish he hadn't. Or
at least they were chagrined that earlier Christians had made Jesus
appear to say it. I am suggesting that originally the scene showed the
disciples themselves bringing Jesus' words back to haunt him. His words
are returning to him worse than void. (Paul also raises the theoretical
possibility of apostles being "false witnesses" in1 Corinthians 15:15.
In the case of the Pillars, he seems to have deemed it no mere
theoretical possibility!)
To these accusations Jesus replies,
"Ask those who have heard me, what I said to them. They know what I
said" (John 18:21). Presumably they are present to be asked, but not the
way the scene reads now. It may once have read differently. Similarly,
when Jesus answers the inquisitor's question "Are you the Christ, the
son of the Blessed One?" and he answers, "You say that I am," is it
possible he is answering Peter, who indeed did say so,
back at Caesarea Philippi? That might make more sense than the mess
exegesis usually makes of Jesus' answer.
When we read in Mark 14:64 that "they
all condemned him as deserving death," I take it to mean all the
disciples, and for the reason Girard gives: the murder must be agreed to
by all. As Benjamin Franklin said, "Gentlemen, if we do not hang
together, we shall all most assuredly hang separately." (Or was that a
community formation? Of course it was: that's the whole point!). Mark, a
later reteller of the tale, tries to get the disciples off stage before
the Sanhedrin scene can begin. He softens "They all condemned him as
deserving death" to "They all forsook him and fled" (Mark 14:50), but
"they" were simply actors running for their dressing rooms to change for
the next scene. And of course he has attributed the condemnation to the
disciples' "monstrous doubles," the Sanhedrin. It is the disciples who
condemned, and who mocked and beat Jesus (Mark 14:65). The irony is all
the more poignant if it his erstwhile disciples who mock his prophetic
abilities and who "received him" (cf. John 1:12)--with their fists.
Was there a second trial, before
Pilate? Probably not. As many have noted, the trial as depicted in the
gospels is pretty much a doublet of the Sanhedrin trial, and the beating
by the guards is the same. So it all reduces to the kangaroo court of
the disciples. As outrageous as a neo-Girardian account may seem,
remember that the Pilate passages seem to many scholars to invite
radical surgery just as urgently as the Sanhedrin texts. If it is hard
to imagine the Sanhedrin holding a trial on the eve of Passover, is it
any more likely for Pontius Pilate to lift a finger to try to save
Jesus, much less to let Barabbas, a known insurrectionist, go free?
And that is far from the only
problem. Behind the Gospel of Peter and Luke's special Passion
material there seems to lie an independent tradition that ascribed the
condemnation and execution not to Pilate, but to Herod Antipas.
(Talmudic tradition even associates the death of Jesus with Alexander
Jannaeus!) If the simple fact of the matter were that Jesus had died at
Pilate's command, how could such a confusion ever have arisen? Perhaps
the story began with something as vague as the statement of
1 Corinthians 2:8 according to which
"the rulers of this world" put Jesus to death. Or perhaps it began with
the disciples doing him in! In any case, it may begin to look like the
place of Herod Antipas and Pontius Pilate in the Passion is no more
secure than that of Herod the Great and Quirinius in the Nativity.
It is common to suggest that the
blame for Jesus' death has been passed from the Romans, whom Christians
thought it best not to offend, to the Jews. But scholars are finding it
increasingly difficult to produce a plausible reason that either Jewish
or Roman authorities should have wanted Jesus dead. Perhaps that is
because neither of them did. The Romans may as easily have been
the secondary scapegoat used by early Christians to shift the blame from
themselves. And that should come as no surprise, the scapegoat game
being what it is. Girard remarks that "there is reason to believe that
the wars described as 'foreign wars' in the mythic narratives were in
fact formerly civil strifes. There are many tales that tell of two
warring cities or nations, in principle independent of one
another--Thebes and Argos, Rome and Alba, Hellas and Troy--whose
conflicts bring to the surface so many elements pertaining directly to
the sacrificial crisis and to its violent resolution that it is hard not
to view these stories as mythic elaborations of this same crisis,
presented in terms of a 'fictive' foreign threat" (1972, 249). I suspect
that the presence of Roman authority in the Passion is a mythic cover-up
of precisely this kind.
Better Him Than Me
The Barabbas incident, however,
demands separate treatment. It does not stand or fall with Pilate's
involvement. Hyam Maccoby's reconstruction of the scene, however, does
involve Pilate. Maccoby ventures that an earlier version of the story
depicted not a weak and vacillating Pilate, trying to pass the buck, but
rather a cruel Roman such as we know Pilate to have been. He did not
offer a choice to the crowd but only rejected their pleadings--for the
release of Jesus! This was in the days before Christians chose Jews to
take the blame for Jesus' death. Once Jews were retroactively drafted as
Christ-killers, however, the story could not be left showing Jews in a
sympathetic light. The solution, Maccoby hypothesizes, was to bifurcate
the Jesus character into Jesus the Nazarene and Jesus Barabbas, and to
have the Jews ask for the release of the wrong one. The original
identity of the two Jesuses is broadly hinted, again, in the coincidence
of the two names. In some Old Latin manuscripts, translated from earlier
Greek originals than we possess, Barabbas appears in Matthew 27:16, 18
as "Jesus Barabbas," and so the New English Bible renders it. And of
course, "Bar-Abbas" looks suspiciously like "Son of the Father."
But there are other possibilities
which present themselves once we dissolve the historical character of
Barabbas. We would have to ask, on Maccoby's reading, why the "wrong"
Jesus is still "Jesus the Son of the Father." This is still too close.
Is it possible to take the text as an early piece of docetism? Could it
have meant that the right Jesus escaped crucifixion? The
result is not too far from the Christian traditions reported by Ibn
Ishaq. But then why would the "wrong" Jesus still be called "the
Christ?" Note that Pilate refers to him in Matthew 27:17, 22 as "Jesus
who is called Christ," a term that admits of some ambiguity,
reminiscent of Josephus' reference to "Jesus the so-called
Christ," or of Luke 3:23, "the son, as was supposed, of Joseph,"
or Romans 8:3, "sending his own son in the likeness of sinful
flesh." Perhaps this means the same thing the Koran says: "They did not
kill him and they did not crucify him but a semblance was made to them"
(4:157).
Docetic interpretations of this sort
are by no means incompatible with the Girardian perspective. The extant
version of the myth of Zeus and the Curetes seems to have undone the
death of the god featured in the hypothesized earlier version. Compared
with a version of the Akedah Isaac hypothesized by several
scholars (Bin Gorion, Sinai und Garazim, 1926, in Maccoby, 1982,
74-86; Spiegel, 57), in which Isaac actually died and was raised, the
present canonical version of Genesis 22 would also qualify as a docetic
rewrite in order to protect the sensibilities of later readers.
But there are a couple of other
elements in the Barabbas story suggesting a different neo-Girardian
version. One is the clear depiction of a crowd howling for the blood of
Jesus. Where such a scene meets us, a scapegoat reading cannot be far
behind. Maccoby rightly says that later Christians could not brook a
scene where Jews clamored for the release of Jesus. My own suggestion
that the story depicted Jesus' own disciples calling for his death
(whether from Pilate or not) seems equally hard to accept, though for
different reasons--except that this has been the traditional reading
until recently! Most readers have always understood the ugly crowd at
the Praetorium to be the same crowd who had hailed Jesus at his entrance
to the city only days before. And this was, as the Gospels clearly
state, a group of disciples and admirers of Jesus. "Ecumenically
correct" exegesis has recently wanted to see the crowd as an unruly
bunch of local pool-hall rowdies and hooligans ("base fellows," Judges
19:22) in an attempt to distance this crowd from Jews or Jerusalemites
in general, so as to shield the latter from Matthew's chilling
imprecation in 27:25. (Whether this maneuver is motivated by interfaith
sensitivity or by face-saving apologetics, I will leave the reader to
decide.) Girard himself identifies the Praetorium crowd with that in the
Triumphal Entry, but he does not make the final step: it was Jesus' own
disciples who put him to death.
The element that Jesus had been
"delivered up out of envy" (Mark 15:10) also has Girardian resonances of
mimetic desire. Suppose we try one of Girard's reversals and posit that
in the earlier version the choice being made here was not which will
live, but rather which will die. And was the choice
originally between only two candidates? Not necessarily. The two Jesuses,
remember, are mimetic twins, mythic ciphers for a condition where,
things having degenerated to a spiral of reciprocal violence, everyone
is everyone else's twin. The victim might as well be anyone, chosen from
the whole group. "Everything suggests a crowd whose intentions were
initially pacific [as on Palm Sunday-RMP]; a disorganized mob that for
unknown reasons (of no real importance to our argument) came to a high
pitch of mass hysteria. The crowd finally hurled itself on one
individual; even though he had no particular qualifications for this
role [i.e., was no more guilty than anyone else], he served to polarize
all the fears, anxieties, and hostilities of the crowd. His violent
death provided the necessary outlet for the mass anguish, and restored
peace" (Girard, 1972, 131).
King for a Day
It is in the scene of the mock
coronation and veneration of Jesus, and his shameful display before the
crowd, that scholars have seen the clearest evidence of Jesus' death as
a ritual scapegoat. In the Roman Saturnalia as in the Babylonia Sacaea
(and many other such rites all over the world, as Frazer and Girard
describe) someone, often a condemned criminal, is chosen to be wined and
dined, waited on and honored, as King of the Wood, King of Fools, etc.
After this, he is summarily executed. Girard rejects Frazer's theory
that such "corn kings" were meant to mime the passing of the seasons.
This imagery did admittedly enter the picture later, as a secondary
association, but, Girard says, the origin of the ceremony must have been
the act of generative violence, the collective murder of the scapegoat.
This is the only way to explain the unique ambivalence of these rites.
Why is the mock king venerated as sacred and yet reviled as a criminal
and unclean? Girard explains: "the king is both very 'bad' and extremely
'good'; the historical alternation of violence and peace is
transferred from time to space" (1972, 268). That is, the ritual mock
king stands for the ancient scapegoat who was regarded simply as a
villain at first, and shown no honors, and subsequently venerated
posthumously. And just as the slain scapegoat is retrospectively
understood as a martyred savior, the later mock king ritual cannot help
but view the whole story of the scapegoat retrospectively. Thus they
already treat the scapegoat-surrogate with a measure of reverence "up
front," before they kill him. Kill him they must, but this time they
know who it is they are about to kill.
Now how are we to relate the mock
king rites to the mockery of the thorn-crowned Jesus? There are a few
options, each with different implications. If we remained blissfully
ignorant of the various history-of-religions parallels, we might be
satisfied to take the Gospels at face value: Jesus has absurdly claimed
to be king, and the rowdy guards mean to show him his folly. But the
close resemblance of the Gospel Passion to the parallels makes this too
simple. Are they just coincidence? The mockery of a poor man with
delusions of royalty is not unattested. In fact, some source or earlier
version of Luke seems to be quoting verbatim from Diodorus Siculus
(34:2, 5-8), who has a character mocking a slave with royal pretensions:
"Remember me when you come into your kingdom." But there is no elaborate
mock king charade here.
Not even Philo's account of the mock
king Carabas (Against Flaccus VI.36-39) helps here. "There was a
certain madman named Carabas..., the sport of idle children and wanton
youths; and they [the Alexandrian mob], driving the poor wretch as far
as the public gymnasium, and setting him up there on high that he might
be seen by everybody, flattened out a leaf of papyrus and put it on his
head instead of a diadem, and clothed the rest of his body with a common
door mat instead of a cloak and instead of a scepter they put in his
hand a small stick of ... papyrus... and when he had been... adorned
like a king, the young men bearing sticks on their shoulders stood on
each side of him instead of spear bearers..., and then others came up,
some as if to salute him, and others as though they wished to plead
their causes before him... Then from the multitude... there arose a...
shout of men calling out 'Maris!'. And this is the name by which it is
said that they call the kings among the Syrians; for they knew that
Agrippa was by birth a Syrian, and also that he was possessed of a great
district of Syria of which he was the sovereign."
Insofar as this rowdy display seems
to be a spontaneous prank, like that of Jesus' Roman mockers on the
traditional reading, it happens not to be directed at any royal claims
of poor Carabas himself, for he made none, but at the actual kingship,
just created by Caligula, of Herod Agrippa I. The crowd staged this
embarrassment for the benefit of Agrippa who was on his way through
Alexandria at the time. And, of course, Carabas was not killed. Had
Jesus' mockery been parallel to that of Carabas, we should expect the
Roman legionaries to have displayed him brazenly before Herod Antipas,
whom Luke does place in Jerusalem at the time, to mock him. But
nothing is said of this.
If one seizes on the eerie similarity
of the name Carabas to that of Barabbas, as some have understandably
done, then the only conclusion is that they represent two local variants
of the title always given to a mock king in one of those rituals, and
that brings us to the next option. Paul Wendland and Sir James Frazer
speculated that the Gospel account is substantially accurate, and
(implicitly) that Jesus was simply the poor joker pressed into service
to play the mock king in a barracks Saturnalia party or to impersonate
Hamaan in a hypothetical Purim adaptation of the Babylonian Sacaea
festival. Though Christian apologists have bristled over this
identification, it is at first hard to see why. One would think the
whole argument a member of the same species as that which tries to
vindicate Matthew's accuracy by demonstrating that the Bethlehem star
was really a supernova or a planetary alignment. The theory would seem
only to add historical plausibility to the Gospel accounts by providing
both historical parallels and a sensible motivation for the soldiers'
action. In fact, for some reason not explained very well, Girard himself
disdained Frazer's view at least partly because it implied the Passion
accounts were first-hand testimony (1978, 169)! What is so disturbing
here?
I suspect the problem is that in this
case apologists could no longer argue, as Nils Dahl did (25-26), that
Jesus must have claimed (at least implicitly) to be the Messiah or he
never would have been executed as "king of the Jews." But on the Frazer/Wendland
theory, Jesus' death as a mock king would imply nothing at all about any
Messianic claims of Jesus. The royalty business would simply be a
function of the cruel ritual in which he had been forced to participate.
Why would this make any difference to Girard either way? Because if
Jesus had merely been forced to play a role in a traditional ritual,
this would seem to compromise the picture of his death as that of a
scapegoat. Girard agrees Jesus was put to death as a scapegoat; he
claims, however, that the Gospels do not accept the scapegoat mechanism
but rather expose it. The problem is that the mock king ritual is too
far removed from the original scapegoating act it commemorates. Its mock
king is merely playing the dramatic role of the scapegoat of the past.
His own death is not that of an actual scapegoat. Rather, it is the
"managed violence" or "sacred," "good violence" of the sacrificial
system founded on the originary violence of long ago. And Girard wants
Jesus himself to have died as a scapegoat, not just playing one.
Girard's view would not exclude the
possibility that Jesus actually did die at a time of sacrificial crisis,
but that the Gospel accounts stem from a subsequent Christian ritual
transformation, a Christian mock king ritual. But there would appear to
be no reason to think Christians ever practiced repeated rites of human
sacrifice--other than symbolically in the eucharist, which involves no
mock king element. Even the later liturgical Passion Plays provide no
help, since they are simply dramatizations of the supposed events of the
Passion, including the mockery as king of the Jews; that is, they
already presuppose the transformation of Jesus' scapegoat death into its
disguised form. They do nothing to effect that transformation.
Is there another option? Some of
Frazer's contemporary critics reacted to his speculations a bit too
vehemently, apparently confusing his ideas with those of the Christ-Myth
school. To this Frazer responded thusly: "The doubts which have been
cast on the historical reality of Jesus are in my judgment unworthy of
serious attention" (Downie, 54). But it might not be so outrageous to
link Girard's theory to the Christ-Myth theory. Girard is happy to cite
and to interpret the most ancient and fantastic myths (and the tragedies
based on them) as dim reflections of actual scapegoat incidents. He does
not for a minute suppose that there was a historical Pentheus, Balder,
Oedipus, Romulus, Dionysus, or Zeus lying behind the myths, only that
these myths (and dramas) stem ultimately from real events about which we
can no longer know anything specific. I am trying to treat the Gospels
as Girard treats these other sources, especially the dramas. These
attempted to rehistoricize their mythic sources in order to provide
verisimilitude by showing the kind of thing that might
have happened, drawing on the customs of their own day. Just as Girard
imagines that Sophocles may have adapted elements of Athenian
pharmakos rites to flesh out his Oedipus cycle, the evangelists may
be imagined to have borrowed details of current Saturnalia rites to
embellish a myth of Jesus the scapegoat savior, since the rite would be
known to their readers and was at least the same kind of thing.
Thus it would have lent a measure of verisimilitude to the dramatized
myth.
I should imagine that for the
purposes of Girard's methodology, it hardly matters whether there had
been a historical Jesus any more than there had been a historical
Oedipus. I am not even sure that Girard's actual views of the Gospels as
a revelation of the scapegoat mechanism (not, as I argue, an example of
it) would require a historical Jesus, even though Girard everywhere
speaks of Jesus himself as the revealer. I suppose a fictional expose of
the scapegoating mechanism would be as genuine a revelation as a
historically based one. He says "the revelation of the founding victim
was first achieved in this text" (1978, 443, emphasis mine).
Baptized in the River Lethe
Girard talks quite a bit about the
willful forgetting on which sacrificial religion is built, the
suppression of the originary violence done to the scapegoat. He claims
that the Gospels have at last revealed the ruse, that "to this day...
that same veil remains unlifted, because only through Christ is it taken
away" (2 Corinthians 3:14). And yet it seems to me that Girard himself
is guilty of trying to draw the veil back over the corpse of the
scapegoat, after having stripped it off for a moment, in that he will
not see how the Gospels embody the scapegoating mechanism instead of
exposing and exploding it. Indeed, the religion of the Cross and the
brutalized victim would seem to be the ultimate epitome and triumph of
what Harry Emerson Fosdick once called "the butcher shop religion of the
fundamentalists." And to pervert the scapegoat theory into an apologetic
for the very thing it tries to expose is a tragic irony indeed. One
might compare Girard with a man who found himself dizzy, teetering on
the edge of the yawning abyss he has uncovered, and then carefully
backing away. He claimed to have found the abyss and could even point
out the location, but as he had been careful to draw the lid back over
it, he had made it once again impossible to see--until one fell into it
unsuspectingly, as people had for many centuries.
Sources Quoted
Gil Bailie, Violence Unveiled,
Humanity at the Crossroads. Crossroad, 1995.
Peter L. Berger, A Rumor of
Angels, Modern Society and the Rediscovery of the Supernatural.
Doubleday, 1970.
Bruce Chilton, "René Girard,
James Williams, and the Genesis of Violence." Bulletin for Biblical
Research 3 (1993) 17-29.
___________, The Temple of Jesus,
His Sacrificial Program Within a Cultural History of Sacrifice. Penn
State Press, 1992.
John B. Cobb, Jr., Christ in a
Pluralistic Age. Westminster, 1975.
John Dominic Crossan, The
Historical Jesus, The Life of a Mediterranean Jewish Peasant.
HarperCollins, 1991.
Nils Alstrup Dahl, The Crucified
Messiah and other Essays. Augsburg, 1974.
Stevan L. Davies, The Revolt of
the Widows, The Social World of the Apocryphal Acts. Southern
Illinois, 1980.
R. Angus Downie, Frazer and the
Golden Bough. Victor Gollancz, 1970.
F. Gerald Downing, Christ and the
Cynics: Jesus and other Radical Preachers in First-Century Tradition.
JSOT, 1988.
______________, Cynics and
Christian Origins. T & T Clark, 1992.
John Drury, Tradition and Design
in Luke's Gospel, A Study in Early Christian Historiography, John Knox,
1976.
Elisabeth Schüssler Fiorenza, In
Memory of Her, A Feminist Theological Reconstruction of Christian
Origins. Crossroad, 1984.
Stanley Fish, Is There a Text in
This Class? The Authority of Interpretive Communities. Harvard,
1980.
Bertil Gärtner, Iscariot.
Fortress, 1971.
René Girard, The Scapegoat.
Johns Hopkins, 1986 (original French, 1982).
_________, Things Hidden Since the
Foundation of the World. Stanford, 1987 (original French, 1978).
_________, Violence and the Sacred.
Johns Hopkins, 1977 (original French, 1972).
Richard J. Golsan, René Girard and
Myth, An Introduction. Garland, 1993.
David R. Griffin, A Process
Christology. Westminster, 1973.
Robert G. Hamerton-Kelly, The
Gospel and the Sacred, Poetics of Violence in Mark. Fortress,
1994.____________________, Sacred Violence, Paul's Hermeneutic of the
Cross. Fortress, 1992.
____________________ (editor),
Violent Origins: Ritual Killing and Cultural Formation. Stanford,
1987,
Scott D. Hill, "The Local Hero in
Palestine in Comparative Perspective," in Robert B. Coote (editor),
Elijah and Elisha in Socioliterary Perspective. Scholars, 1992,
37-74.
Adolf Holl, Jesus in Bad Company.
Avon, 1974.
Richard A. Horsley, Jesus and the
Spiral of Violence. Popular Jewish Resistance in Roman Palestine.
Fortress, 1993.
Werner H. Kelber, Mark's Story of
Jesus. Fortress, 1979.
Frank Kermode, The Genesis of
Secrecy, On the Interpretation of Narrative. Harvard, 1979.
Hans Küng, On Being a Christian.
Doubleday, 1976.
Hyam Maccoby, Judas Iscariot and
the Myth of Jewish Evil. Free Press, 1992.
____________, The Sacred
Executioner: Human Sacrifice and the Legacy of Guilt. Thames and
Hudson, 1982.
Gilbert Murray, Five Stages of
Greek Religion. Doubleday, 1951.
Dennis E. Nineham, The Gospel of
Saint Mark. Penguin, 1963.
Wolfhart Pannenberg, Jesus-God and
Man. 2nd ed., Westminster, 1977.
Neal Robinson, Christ in Islam and
Christianity. State University of New York, 1991.
E.P. Sanders, Jesus and Judaism.
Fortress, 1985.
Raymund Schwager, Must There Be
Scapegoats? Violence and Redemption in the Bible. Harper & Row, 1987
(original German, 1978).
Lucien Scubla, "The Christianity of
René Girard and the Nature of Religion," in Paul Dumouchel (editor),
Violence and Truth, On the Work of René Girard. Athlone Press, 1988,
160-178.
Shalom Spiegel, The Last Trial, On
the Legends and Lore of the Command to Abraham to Offer Isaac as a
Sacrifice: The Akedah. Jewish Lights, 1993.
Gerd Theissen, Social Reality and
the Early Christians: Theology, Ethics, and the World of the New
Testament. Fortress, 1992.
___________, Sociology of Early
Palestinian Christianity. Fortress, 1978.
Tzvetan Todorov, The Poetics of
Prose. Cornell, 1977.
Theodore J. Weeden,
Mark-Traditions in Conflict. Fortress, 1971
James G. Williams, The Bible,
Violence, and the Sacred, Liberation from the Myth of Sanctioned
Violence. HarperCollins, 1991.
By Robert M. Price
===================
Δεν υπάρχουν σχόλια:
Δημοσίευση σχολίου